In What Way Does Logic Involve Necessity?

ABSTRACT

In this paper I advance an account of the necessity of logic in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. I reject both the “metaphysical” reading of Peter Hacker, who takes Tractarian logical necessity to consist in the mode of truth of tautologies, and the “resolute” account of Cora Diamond, who argues that all Tractarian talk of necessity is to be thrown away. I urge an alternative conception based on remarks 3.342 and 6.124. Necessity consists in what is not arbitrary (nicht willkürlich), and contingency in what is up to our arbitrary choice (willkürlich), in the symbols we use, in how we picture or model the world. Necessity is not a mode of truth of propositions, but lies in the requirements of their intelligibility. I argue that this conception is implicit in certain “resolute” readings and in some of their critics. Both sides of the dispute are committed to certain logical features of language or thought, patterns of symbolizing constitutive of intelligibility that are not up to us to institute or alter. This conception of non-arbitrary patterns of symbolizing, I argue, is what logical syntax in the Tractatus consists in. I also argue that the well-known Tractarian view of propositions as truth-functions of elementary propositions can be understood in terms of patterns of norms governing our making sense with the affirmation and denial of propositions. [End Page 289]

INTRODUCTION

That logic has something to do with necessity is one of the longest-running ideas in the history of philosophy. According to Aristotle a “deduction (συλλογισμὸς) is a discourse in which, certain things having been supposed, something different from the things supposed results of necessity (ἐξ ἀνάγκης)” (1989, 24b18–20, 2). On the other side of the historical spectrum, we are, nowadays, often told of how Saul Kripke discovered that there is metaphysical, in addition to logical, necessity; a claim that obviously presupposes that logic is connected with necessity. Does the Tractatus agree with this tradition? That’s the central question of this essay.1

I will approach this question by considering two of the main opponents in the recent debate over “resolute” approaches to reading the Tractatus. On one side, Peter Hacker advances a positive answer. He takes one of Wittgenstein’s principal criticisms of Frege and Russell to be that they don’t have a coherent explanation of the necessity of logic, and he holds that the Tractatus’s “most significant achievement” is its “account of logical necessity,” which overcomes the incoherence of the Frege-Russell view (Hacker 1986, 42). On the other side, Cora Diamond seems to return an unequivocally negative answer. In “Throwing Away the Ladder,” the founding document of resolution, she takes 6.37, “Es gibt nur eine logische Notwendigkeit,”2 to be “ironically self-destructive,” since “[i]n so far as we grasp what Wittgenstein aims at, . . . we shall not imagine necessities as states of affairs at all. We throw away the sentences about necessity; they really are, at the end, entirely empty” (Diamond 1988, 198). On this reading it seems the Tractatus espouses, to put it in contemporary parlance, an unqualified modal eliminativism.

I will argue against resting with either of these interpretations. In section I I show that Hacker’s account suffers from two significant drawbacks: it rests on a misreading of Frege’s and Russell’s views, and, in the context of his overall interpretation of the Tractatus, the conception of logical necessity he attributes to Wittgenstein falls prey to the same problems that he finds in Frege and Russell. It is not altogether clear what Diamond takes to be the considerations leading to modal eliminativism in the Tractatus. However, in section II I reconstruct a line of argument from the fundamental Tractarian logical distinction between names and sentences to the incoherence of at least the grounds of the view that the propositions of logic—tautologies and contradiction—are necessary in virtue of the special way in which they are determined as true or false. But, in this argument and in Hacker’s reading, logic is conceived of as tautologies and contradictions, and necessity is conceived of as a special mode of truth. These conceptions are not mandatory. In section III I will urge an alternative conception of necessity and contingency in the terms of 6.124, “manches an den Symbolen, die wir gebrauchen, wäre willkürlich, manches nicht.”3 That is, necessity lies in what is not arbitrary (nicht willkürlich), and contingency in what is up to our arbitrary choice (willkürlich), in the symbols we use, in how we picture or model the world. Necessity here is not a mode of truth of propositions, but lies in the requirements of the intelligibility of propositions. [End Page 290] In section IV I flesh out this conception by showing that it is implicit in Diamond’s and James Conant’s account of the Tractarian view of nonsense. I also argue that it is equally implicit in an account of the Tractatus’s treatment of Russell’s Paradox due to two critics of the resolute approach: Ian Proops and Peter Sullivan. These accounts are committed to certain logical features of language or thought, patterns of symbolizing constitutive of intelligibility of propositions, that are not up to us to institute or alter. Of the many notions of logic or the logical in the Tractatus, the one most closely involving this conception of necessity is logical syntax; as I understand it, Tractarian logical syntax consists of the non-arbitrary features of modeling the world with propositions. This constitutes no more than the beginnings of a defense of the claim that logic in the Tractatus does involve necessity. If the defense is to have any substance, one has to show how, in the text, the idea of the non-arbitrary is connected with the idea of patterns of symbolizing. In section V I outline an account of this connection, based on an attempt to understand some puzzling remarks in the 5.47s and 5.51s. The central idea of this account, developed by considering some texts of Frege from a Tractarian perspective, is a view of what it is for a proposition to be a truth-function: it is for two things that are done with propositional-signs—affirming and denying them—to be subject to standards of correctness that fall in specific patterns. These are the patterns of logical syntax, features of propositions in which the necessities and impossibilities of logic show forth.4

I. HACKER ON THE NECESSITY OF TAUTOLOGIES

Hacker’s writings suggest that he regards Frege and Russell as, at best, philosophical village idiots with more or less indistinguishable views. In the case of logic, they painted themselves into a corner with two commitments. First, the “apodeictic status” of “laws of logic” “was clear enough” to them (Hacker 1986, 44), in the sense that for them the propositions of logic are true in a special way, true “come what may, under all conditions” (ibid., 47). But, second, they took the propositions of logic to have “a subject-matter,” namely, “the most general features of the world” or “the properties and relations of logical objects or constants” (ibid., 38). In order to render these two commitments consistent, they made the subject matter of logic into a special, necessary, kind of facts: facts about the maximally general features of the world, which cannot fail to be a part of any possible world, or facts about logical objects, which have the properties they have and stand in the relations they stand no matter how else the world might be.5

But through this maneuver “neither Frege nor Russell could coherently explain” “what gives [logical laws] their necessitarian status” (ibid., 44). The reason is that, by giving logical propositions a subject matter, they “bargained away the necessity of such propositions (since completely general propositions may nevertheless be only accidentally valid)” (ibid., 38). So far as I can tell, the parenthetical remark just [End Page 291] quoted is the only explanation Hacker ever gives for the incoherence of the Frege-Russell account of logical necessity. A contrast between accidental and essential of course figures prominently in the Tractatus’s remarks on logic (see, e.g., 2.012, 6.031(2), and 6.1232). It seems that for Hacker what the contrast amounts to is obvious, perhaps because he takes it as obvious that facts, however general, remain what happens to be the case in the world, since we can always conceive of the world as containing a different set of facts.6 If all facts are contingent, no type of facts can ground the necessity of any truth. Hence the Frege-Russell account of logical necessity is patently inadequate.

Wittgenstein’s alternative rests on characterizing the propositions of logic as tautologies. Hacker’s interpretation of the Tractatus is a representative instance of the familiar view of that book as containing a “metaphysics of logical atomism” (1986, 55) and an account of “the essential nature of representation” (ibid., 32). The notion of tautology is a consequence of the nature of propositional representation of the world. All propositions are uniquely analyzable into logically independent elementary “propositional-sign[s]” (ibid.) Each of these “is essentially a description of a (possible) state of affairs. If the state of affairs described obtains, the proposition is true, otherwise it is false” (ibid.). So “[t]ruth and falsity . . . are essential properties of ” elementary propositions. Moreover, these propositions are “bipolar, i.e. capable of being true and capable of being false (so there are no necessary truths or necessary falsehoods among elementary propositions)” (ibid.). Hacker doesn’t specify what non-elementary propositions describe. But he does offer a gloss on Tractatus 5—Der Satz ist eine Wahrheitsfunktion der Elementarsätze: the “truth-value of a proposition . . . is a function of (is dependent on) the truth-value(s) of ” elementary propositions (ibid., 44). What Hacker has in mind may then be this. Non-elementary propositions are expressed by signs in which occur logical connectives joining propositional-signs. Wittgenstein rejects Frege’s view of propositions as names of truth-values, and of logical connectives as names of functions from truth-values to truth-values (ibid., 41). So non-elementary propositions are not descriptions of possible states of affairs consisting of combinations of truth-values and truth-functions. What they depict, rather, are the possibilities of existence and nonexistence of the states of affairs pictured by elementary propositions (4.2). The world is the totality of states of affairs that exist, so a possibility of existence and nonexistence of the states of affairs is a possible state of the world. That is, a non-elementary proposition represents a set of possible states of the world. If any of those possible states exist, then the proposition is true; otherwise it’s false. Since the truth or falsity of an elementary proposition corresponds to, i.e., is determined by, the existence or nonexistence respectively of the state of affairs it represents (4.25), a possible state of the world corresponds to a possible combination of truth and falsity of elementary propositions. Thus what a proposition represents corresponds to a set of truth-possibilities of elementary propositions (4.4), and a proposition is true if any truth-possibility of elementary propositions with which it agrees obtains, [End Page 292] false otherwise. That’s the reason why the truth-value of a proposition is determined by, i.e., is a function of, the truth-values of elementary propositions, which are the arguments of that function.

Given this account of what non-elementary propositions represent, and so of how they are determined as true or false, it follows that they are not essentially bipolar. For given any set of elementary propositions, there is a function whose value is truth for every possible combination of truth-values of those elementary propositions. The non-elementary propositions whose truth-values are determined by that function of truth-values of elementary propositions are tautologies, and they are true in every truth-possibility of elementary propositions, i.e., every possible state of the world. A tautology is thus “true . . . under all conditions” (ibid., 47), i.e., a necessary truth. But this failure of bipolarity means that a tautology “has no truth-conditions,” and is not a genuine proposition describing possible states of affairs, but rather a “limiting” or “degenerate” proposition which “describe[s] nothing” (ibid., 51).

Somewhat surprisingly, Hacker never spells out explicitly why this account of logical necessity overcomes the incoherence of the Frege-Russell account. Presumably the reason is precisely the combination of necessity and emptiness of tautologies. The requirements for a tautology to be true are invariably fulfilled, fulfilled in all possible worlds, so even though a tautology has no truth conditions, it is true in the special kind of way demanded by logic. But the reason why it is true in this special way is not because it describes a special type of invariably obtaining situations. It is, rather, because of the way in which the truth-values of non-elementary propositions are determined by the possible truth-values of elementary propositions. Thus, it is the nature of propositional representation, rather than features of the world or of all possible worlds, that makes tautologies true. So the explanation of the necessity of tautologies does not run afoul of the thesis that any worldly fact or state of affairs is contingent.

I turn now to detail two problems with Hacker’s account. First, Hacker misrepresents Frege’s and Russell’s views of the relation between modality and logic. Let me begin with the more serious misrepresentation, that of Russell. In a(n admittedly unpublished) paper, “Necessity and Possibility,” Russell writes, “the subject of modality ought to be banished from logic” (1994, 520). The reason he gives in this paper is that “there is no such comparative and superlative of truth as is implied by the notions of contingency and necessity” (ibid.), a reason echoed in Principles of Mathematics: “there seems to be no true proposition of which there is any sense in saying that it might have been false. . . . What is true, is true; what is false, is false; and concerning fundamentals, there is nothing more to be said” (1903, 454). This doesn’t quite have the ring of a commitment to logic having a special, necessary, mode of truth. Now, in “Necessity and Possibility” Russell also offers four accounts of necessity. For example, a proposition is necessary if it can be deduced from the axioms of logic.7 So Russell’s considered view in this period is not quite that modal notions are to be “banished” because there is no such thing [End Page 293] as necessity, but rather that they are explicable in various different ways, but always in terms of more fundamental logical notions.8

Frege is not quite so strident as Russell about banishing modality, but he does insist in Begriffsschrift §4 (1879, 3–4) that his notion of conceptual content does not distinguish between the traditional notions of apodeictic and assertoric judgments.9 Moreover, in the same way as Russell, Frege outlines accounts of traditional modal judgments in logical terms. For example, “Das apodiktische Urtheil unterscheidet sich vom assertorischen dadurch, dass das Bestehen allgemeiner Urtheile angedeutet wird, aus denen [sie] geschlossen werden kann,” so that “[w]enn ich einen Satz als nothwendig bezeichne, so gebe ich dadurch einen Wink über meine Urtheilsgründe” (ibid., 3). Frege’s account seems to be that the occurrence of a predicate of necessity in the expression of a judgment affects only what he would later call the tone or illumination of what is expressed, but not its sense. If so then perhaps there is no objective standard for assessing the correctness of an apodeictic judgment distinct from those standards applying to its assertoric counterpart. That is, there is no case where judging that p is correct but judging that necessarily p is incorrect because there are no universal judgments from which p follows.

The upshot is that Russell and Frege took logic to be philosophically fundamental, and to have no need for modal notions: the laws of logic need not be stated using modal expressions, nor does the nature of logic involve modal concepts. But, they were not wholesale eliminativists about modality. Rather, they were modal reductionists, willing to countenance modality to the extent that it is explicable in terms of the concepts of logic.10

Obviously Hacker’s misreading of Frege and Russell11 doesn’t invalidate his account of the Tractatus, since Wittgenstein may have shared that misunderstanding,12 and developed his view of logic on its basis. But there is a second and more serious problem with Hacker’s interpretation: his account of logical necessity in terms of tautology doesn’t in fact overcome the purported incoherence of the supposed Fregean-Russellian conception of logical necessity. The account rests on two claims:

(BP) Elementary propositions are bipolar.

(TF) Propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions.

From these two assumptions it follows that there exist non-elementary propositions that are true for all truth-values of elementary propositions. What is the status of (TF)? Is it not a generalization about all non-elementary propositions? Does it not then state or describe a general feature of such propositions? If so, then the question is: is this a necessary or a contingent feature?

At least two aspects of Hacker’s views suggest that it is necessary for propositions to be truth-functions of elementary propositions. First, Wittgenstein’s solution to the problem of logical necessity is supposed to be that logical truth is “essential validity” (Hacker 1986, 47), which I take to mean truth that follows [End Page 294] from the essence of propositional representation. Now (BP), as we saw, is expressly claimed to describe an essential feature of elementary propositions. It’s hard to see how (TF) could fail to describe an essential feature of propositions, since it is also required to account for the existence of tautologies. So it seems that propositions don’t just happen to be truth-functions, but are necessarily truth-functions. Second, from a Fregean, if not exactly Frege’s, perspective, one can take (TF) to be a theory of the contents of non-elementary propositions: they express functions from truth-possibilities of elementary propositions to truth-values. Hacker, I take it, would say that there is still a fundamental difference between such a Fregean view and Wittgenstein’s account: the Fregean would take these functions to be part of the reality described by non-elementary propositions, while Wittgenstein holds that the sum total of reality is exhaustively described by elementary propositions, so that these functions are not part of the reality described but merely play a role in non-elementary descriptions of that same reality. But why should we think that this difference is more than terminological? After all, whether or not the functions are part of the reality described, they play a role in fixing the truth requirements of the propositions in question. This suggests that the significance of being a part of the reality described lies in Hacker’s assumption that whatever is described by an ordinary proposition is contingent. So Hacker must hold that it is not contingent, not a mere fact about language, that propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions.

But now the question arises, in what sense is it necessary that propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions? It’s hard to make out that it is logically necessary, for it’s hard to see that (TF) is (expressed by) a tautology. Since 6.37 suggests that all necessity is logical, there is, prima facie, a problem. Hacker has a way out of this initial problem, since, like Diamond, he also has qualms about 6.37, albeit not on the same grounds. He writes, “it is misleading . . . to say that all necessity is logical necessity, since after all most of the propositions of the Tractatus itself seem to state . . . metaphysical necessities about the nature and essence of reality, of any possible world” (1986, 51). So perhaps (TF) can be understood as describing a metaphysically rather than logically necessary feature of non-elementary propositions. This way out, however, runs into another problem. Central to Hacker’s interpretation of the Tractatus is the claim that Tractarian metaphysical necessities are “ineffable” (ibid.), but Hacker maintains, in addition and in criticism of the Tractatus, that these ineffable metaphysical necessities are “every bit as brutish as brute empirical facts” (ibid.). So (TF) describes an ineffable necessary fact about propositions. In order for this not to contradict the principle that all facts are contingent, Hacker would have to maintain that there are two kinds of necessity: the necessity of tautologies and the necessity of metaphysical facts about representation. Moreover, the latter undergirds the former, at least in the sense that if propositions were not necessarily truth-functions of elementary propositions, then there wouldn’t be the special kind of truth of tautologies. Now, this isn’t quite the supposed Frege-Russell view of logical necessity, but it’s [End Page 295] unclear how much it differs: logical propositions are necessarily true, not in virtue of depicting necessary features of the world, but in virtue of there being certain necessary features of language.13 Finally, is it clear that the fact that propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions is any more necessary than the fact that matter is composed of elementary particles?

II. DIAMOND ON THE IMPLOSION OF MODAL TALK

As noted, Diamond apparently holds that understanding Wittgenstein results in realizing the emptiness of all sentences about necessity, including such remarks of the Tractatus as 6.37. From “Throwing Away the Ladder,” however, it’s not clear that the anti-modal stance she discerns in the Tractatus is quite so unqualified. Diamond begins her discussion of necessity in section 3 by saying that Wittgenstein consistently opposes conceptions of “necessity imaged as fact,” as what is “the case,” albeit in all possible worlds (1988, 195). This leaves it open that Wittgenstein would not be opposed to non-factual images of necessity. Now, it is of course a centerpiece of Diamond’s resolute approach precisely to reject Hacker’s ineffable Tractarian necessities, and as we have just noted, Hacker himself declares these to be (like) brute (empirical) facts. But Hacker’s ineffable necessities are metaphysical. What about the necessity of logic? Can it be conceived non-factually?

To address this question, let’s turn to Diamond’s account of tautology. She begins by sketching a view of logic Wittgenstein rejects, in which the necessity of logic is factual: “[i]t is overwhelmingly natural to say . . . that, if we fix the meaning of the sentential connectives, . . . then a sentence of the form ‘p or not p’ . . . has truth conditions which are in all possible circumstances fulfilled” (ibid., 192). Wittgenstein’s contrasting view is that there is

a rule determining the logical features of the comparison with reality of . . . genuine sentences formed from genuine sentences. That fundamental rule will really be the meaning, all rolled up into one, as it were, of all the logical constants. And if we grasp that, we shall not be tempted to think of tautologies and contradictions as saying that something or other is the case. We shall not be tempted really to think of them as sentences.

(Ibid., 192–93)

This fundamental rule requires elementary propositions and the operation N, “a method of construction of sentences from sentences” (ibid., 193).14 There is no explanation of the fundamental rule in this paper, but one obvious view is that it applies to the outputs of the method of construction, specifying how they are to be compared with reality in terms of agreement and disagreement with the truth possibilities of those elementary sentences that occur in their constructional history. Applied to certain outputs of the method, tautologies, the rule, by itself, determines these “sentence-like constructions” as true; applied to others, contradictions, the rule by itself determines them as false. They are not “genuine sentences” because [End Page 296] their truth or falsity is not the result of “comparison to reality” (ibid., 193) effected by elementary propositions, but fixed by the fundamental rule alone.

Diamond goes on to say that “[l]ogical necessity is that of tautologies”:

It is not that they are true because their truth conditions are met in all possible worlds, but because they have none. ‘True in all possible worlds’ does not describe one special case of truth conditions being met but specifies the logical character of certain sentence-like constructions formulable from sentences.

(Ibid., 198)

Does logical necessity then consist in the “logical character” of tautologies? If so, is this conception of logical necessity an image of necessity as fact? This passage suggest that Diamond is offering an explanation, as opposed to elimination, of the phrase ‘true in all possible worlds’, an explanation in terms of the way in which tautologies are determined as true, their logical character.15 Through this analysis, we can see that tautologies do not owe their necessity to truly describing what is the case in all possible worlds; hence the logical character of tautologies provides a non-factual image of logical necessity.

There are four parallels between this account and Hacker’s reading. First, what Diamond calls “genuine sentences” and Hacker “non-degenerate propositions” require, for their truth, comparison with reality. Call these ordinary sentences. Second, Wittgenstein rejects the idea that the sentences of logic, just like ordinary sentences, require comparison with reality for truth, and the idea that the necessity of logic consists of successful comparison with, not just actual but all possible, realities. So, third, the tautologies of logic are not ordinary propositions but proposition-like sequences of words with the property that the rule specifying the requirements for non-elementary propositions to be true, by itself, determines that these requirements are met for them, without comparison with reality. Finally, this “logical character” of tautologies constitutes their necessity. Given these parallels, it’s not clear why and how, if we stop “imagining necessities as states of affairs,” we should reach the apparently unqualified conclusion that “sentences about necessity are entirely empty.” Why, in other words, is this view of tautology merely another rung on the ladder?

How Diamond might answer this question only becomes clear in a later paper, “Truth before Tarski” (2002), where she develops further her reading of how, by thinking through doctrines apparently advanced in the Tractatus, one can see that they are empty. The particular “implosion,” to use Warren Goldfarb’s term for this form of Tractarian self-undermining (see 1997, 70), concerns Wittgenstein’s apparent view of the fundamental logical differences between propositions and names. The starting point is a much-quoted passage from the Notes on Logic:

Let us consider symbols of the form ‘xRy’; to these correspond primarily pairs of objects, of which one has the name ‘x,’ the other the name ‘y.’ The x’s and y’s stand in various relations to each other, among others the relation R holds between some, but not between others. I now determine the sense of ‘xRy’ by laying down: when the facts behave in regard to [sich verhaltern zu] ‘xRy’ so that the meaning of ‘x’ stands in [End Page 297] the relation R to the meaning of ‘y,’ then I say that [the facts] are ‘of like sense’ [‘gleichsinnig’] with the proposition ‘xRy’; otherwise, ‘of opposite sense’ [‘entgegengesetzt’]; I correlate the facts to the symbol ‘xRy’ by thus dividing them into those of like sense and those of opposite sense.

(Wittgenstein 1979, 104[6])

Following Thomas Ricketts (1996), Diamond takes the sense of ‘xRy’ to be a “rule” for comparing the way in which the signs (letters) making up this sentence are arranged with the way in which the objects named by ‘x’ and ‘y’ are related:

When the object named by the name standing to the left of ‘R’ . . . stands in relation R to the object named by the name standing to the right of ‘R’, this ‘behavior of the facts’ shall count as like in sense (gleichsinnig) with the proposition ‘xRy’; otherwise the facts count as opposite in sense to the proposition.

(Diamond 2002, 268)

Diamond adds the idea that the rule for comparison has a “direction” which can be “reversed.” We can take it that the idea is based on 4.0621—“die Zeichen ‘p’ und ‘~p’ das gleiche sagen können,” and 5.2341(3)—“Die Verneinung verkehrt den Sinn des Satzes.” To begin with, if R is an asymmetrical relation, then we can use the same sign, ‘xRy’, to say that the objects named by ‘x’ and ‘y’ stand in the converse relation of R, by adopting a rule of comparing this sign with the fact that interchanges “like sense” with “opposite sense” in the original rule. With the new rule, the facts agree with the sign just in case “the name standing to the right of ‘R’ names an object that stands in R to the object named by the name to the left of ‘R’” (ibid.). Wittgenstein then moves to the reversible directionality of all propositions by an analogy: we can use a sign ‘p’ to say what its negation, ‘~p’, says merely by adopting a rule of comparison interchanging what facts count as of like sense with what facts count as of opposite sense in the original rule. The logical criterion for being a proposition is this reversible directionality”; the use of names, in contrast, “has no intrinsic capacity for reversal[,] no directionality” (ibid., 269).

Diamond argues that this criterion of propositionhood leads to a phenomenon parallel to what is sometimes called the Kerry paradox (see Frege 1967a [1892]): because for Frege an expression, as a matter of logic, can refer to a concept only if it is used as a predicate, and not as a proper name, “there are ways of attempting to talk about a concept that are self-defeating, in that we put what we want to be an expression for a concept in the logical place for a proper name, whereupon it is no longer the expression for a concept” (2002, 269). Correspondingly, on Wittgenstein’s logical criterion for being a proposition,

attempting to speak of a proposition as one can speak of names, or attempting to treat it in other ways as a name, that is, by putting it into a slot where the subject of a predicate goes, or where the name of one of the terms of a relation goes, will result in its no longer being, logically speaking, a proposition. It will lack directionality.

(Ibid.)

But talk of ways of comparing propositions with reality requires precisely treating propositions as standing in some relation to reality. Thus, [End Page 298]

following out the implications of what Wittgenstein tells us about the relation between our propositions and reality lands us, and is meant to land us, in incoherence. . . . All such attempts . . . involve thinking of propositions as items going into a relation as its terms, that is, not as genuinely directional, not as genuinely capable of propositional sense. Such talk can be understood to dissolve when we understand that what we are trying to do is to treat a proposition as nameable, as a logical subject, and when we understand the self-defeatingness of that aim.

(Ibid., 270)

On the basis of this implosion we can see why on Diamond’s view the Tractarian account of tautology is supposed to be thrown away. Part of that account is set forth in sentences like:

Non-elementary propositions are compared with reality by agreeing or disagreeing with truth-possibilities of elementary propositions.

This sentence seems to be a generalization about propositions, each of whose instances, e.g.,

If ‘Frege was born in Wismar’ is a non-elementary proposition then ‘Frege is born in Wismar’ is compared with reality by agreeing or disagreeing with truth-possibilities of elementary propositions,

describes a proposition as standing in the relation of comparison to reality. So the apparent account of what qualifies a proposition as a tautology has in fact to speak of propositions in such a way that they are not “genuinely directional, not genuinely capable of propositional sense,” and so not really as propositions at all.

Before going on, I want to register a doubt about this implosion. It’s not clear that the account of tautology needs to be understood as attempting to speak of propositions, as opposed to propositional-signs. According to 3.12, “der Satz ist das Satzzeichen in seiner projektiven Beziehung zur Welt.” So why can’t we take the Notes on Logic passage as a description of how propositional-signs are compared with the world, a statement of those signs’ projective relation to the world? Reversible directionality of comparison would then be a feature of propositional-signs’ projective relation, not of propositions’. Similarly the clause of the theory of tautology cited above can be understood as a statement of how non-elementary propositional-signs are projectively related to the world.

As I understand Diamond, we are not meant merely to recognize the dissolution of talk about the relation of propositions to reality: “What is left, when we recognize the self-defeatingness of such talk, is our understanding and operating with the senseful sentences of our language” (ibid.). Although Diamond is not explicit about this, it seems that on her view this understanding and operating is connected with certain “logical features of the use of ordinary sentences, logical patterns of use,” and the Tractatus aims to “redirect[] our attention” to these features or patterns, through our recognition of the emptiness of semantic talk (ibid., 259). The model for the view is Frege, as interpreted by Peter Geach, and by Ricketts and Goldfarb.16 On Goldfarb’s and Ricketts’s reading of Frege, in particular, the apparent ontological [End Page 299] and semantic talk involved in the Kerry phenomenon—e.g., proper names refer to objects, not concepts—is really “supervenient” (Ricketts 1986, 65) on patterns of inferential relations that “articulate” or “redescribe” our inchoate grasp of logical features “present in ordinary informative discourse” (Diamond 2002, 257). These patterns of inference are the bases for identifying “parts and features of statements as logically functioning units” (Goldfarb 1997, 60–61); they “inflict” a logical segmentation on sentences. The criterion for a part of a sentence to be a proper name is that that sub-sentential sign plays certain roles in at least the inferential patterns of first-order universal and existential generalization, and Leibniz’s Law.17 Function names are isolated on the basis of second- and higher-order patterns of inference. In giving up such apparent claims as that the ontological category of object is determined by being the referent of proper names, then, we are left with and “redirected” back to the patterns of valid inference that are the logical basis of being a proper name.

So what are the inferential patterns that we are left with when we throw away the talk of reversible directionality? Diamond considers two proposals. One is Geach’s logic of duality (1982), which attempts to make more precise what it is for p and ‘~p’ to say the same. For every language L there exists a dual language LD, with the same vocabulary and syntax, such that each sentence of LD “equiform” with a sentence of L says the contradictory opposite of that sentence of L. The logical distinction between proposition and name is based on features of a compositional translation from sentences of L to their duals in LD that preserves what is said. In such a translation sentences of L are mapped to their negations, negations to the subsentence negated, conjunctions to disjunctions, etc. But names are mapped to themselves; names are self-dual. The logical criterion of sentencehood is thus non-self-duality.

Diamond’s own proposal is this. Talk about propositions agreeing or disagreeing with reality directs us to inferences from ascriptions of beliefs and what is the case to the correctness of beliefs:

A believes pp So A’s belief is correct

A believes p not-p So A’s belief is incorrect.

(Ibid., 260)

Presumably judgment and assertion can take the place of belief. What about reversible directionality? That talk directs us to a feature of those inferences: their correctness “depend[s] on the rules governing the judgment-verb” (ibid., 270). This feature is exhibited in an example about

the verb ‘to doubt’. To say in English that A doubts p means that A rather thinks that p is not the case; to say in Scots . . . that A doubts p means that A rather thinks or fears that p is the case. The difference between the two uses of ‘doubts’ is nothing but the difference in the rules for how we may infer: [End Page 300]

[In English

  A doubts we shall be late   We shall be late   So A is wrong

is valid. In Scots

  A doubts we shall be late   We shall be late,   A is right

is valid.] This is to say that there is no difference between the English and the Scots sentences except the direction of comparison. . . . The slot into which we put the proposition which A judges, after the words ‘A judges that’ or ‘A doubts that’ (etc.) is not a slot for a relatum but for a proposition, as is shown by the fact that, without there being any alteration in the meaning of any component of the proposition in question . . . , we have two opposite ways of operating logically with the resulting proposition. That is, from ‘p’ we can infer in two opposite directions to . . . the correctness or incorrectness of what [A] is said to hold.

(Ibid., 270–71)

That this inferential feature underlies reversible directionality leads to a worry about Diamond’s implosion. Diamond’s example makes it clear that from the fact that a sentence occurs in another in a position that looks like a placeholder of some relation expression it doesn’t follow that in that occurrence the sentence is logically a name rather than a proposition. So, even if the account of tautology has to contain statements in which propositions occur (as opposed to mentioning propositional-signs) it is not immediately obvious that these statements are self-defeating. It all depends on whether those occurrences function logically as propositions, and that is a matter of whether and how those statements occur in valid inferences.

This point leads to another worry. Even if this line of argument succeeds in showing that the account of tautology is self-defeating, it’s not clear that it thereby shows that all sentences (apparently) about necessity are empty. Consider especially the sentences of the second degree of modal involvement, in which a modal sentential operator is attached to what is grammatically a sentence, e.g., “it is necessary that water is H2O.” Such sentences seem to ascribe properties to propositions, or to the states of affairs they depict. Do the embedded sentences function logically as names or as propositions? Well, if we go with Geach’s logic of duality, the answer seems to be yes. Like Diamond, Geach holds that sentences used to ascribe beliefs occur logically as propositions in the ascription sentences. His argument rests on the claim that the dual of a sentence forming operator φ is ⌜¬φ¬⌝. Where φ is ‘A believes that’, if we assume that p is not self-dual in ‘A believes that p’, we obtain as its dual, ‘A does not believe that it’s not the case that not-p’. Accepting the elimination of the double negation, we obtain ‘A does not believe that p’, which is clearly the contradictory in the original language of ‘A believes that p’ and so its dual. Consider now the case where φ is ‘necessarily’. Again assuming that p is not self-dual in ‘necessarily p’, we obtain as its dual, ‘it’s not necessary that it’s not the case that not-p’, [End Page 301] i.e., either ‘it’s not necessary that p’ or ‘possibly not-p’, both of which are clearly duals of the original sentence. An analogous argument works for ‘possibly’.18

I don’t know if a similar case can be made on Diamond’s views. One point we can make is this. As we have seen, on her view the cash value of talk about propositions agreeing with reality are inferences from ascriptions of beliefs and what is the case to the correctness of beliefs. So we might ask, why isn’t the cash value of talk about necessary and possible states of affair the validity of the following patterns of inference:

  • p, so ‘possibly p’ is true and ‘necessarily not-p’ is false.

  • • not-p, so ‘necessarily p’ is false and ‘possibly not-p’ is true.

  • • A believes that necessarily p, not-p, so A is wrong.

  • • A believes that p is impossible, p, so A is wrong.

Of course, these patterns don’t show that sentences occur in logically reversible ways in modal contexts; for that one would have to make the metaphor of reversibility applicable to modal inferential patterns. I don’t know if that can be done, but I’m not concerned to establish that embedded sentences in modal contexts are logically sentences. I claim only that without further investigation of the logic of such modal sentences, we’re not entitled to conclude that they are empty.

III. THE NON-ARBITRARY AS A CONCEPTION OF LOGICAL SYNTAX

Let’s take stock. Neither Hacker’s explicit account of logical necessity in the Tractatus nor Diamond’s account (as I reconstruct it) of the Tractatus’s rejection of necessity tout court is fully satisfactory. On the one hand, Hacker’s account of tautology as an explanation of the necessity logic fails on its own terms. On the other, Diamond’s rejection of what seems to be essentially the same account is inconclusive. In order to make further progress, let’s begin by noting a common assumption underlying these opposed readings of the Tractatus. Both accept that taking the propositions of logic to be tautologies offers an explanation of the non-factual necessity of these propositions. This amounts to accepting that the primary notion of necessity applying to logic is that the sentences of logic are necessarily true; tautology comes in as an explanation of this special mode of truth. In this and the next section I will explore a different conception of necessity in the Tractatus, having to do, not with a mode of truth, but with requirements of intelligible discourse.

There are two anchors for this conception. First, 6.124:

Wir sagten, manches an den Symbolen, die wir gebrauchen, wäre will-kürlich, manches nicht. In der Logik drückt nur dieses aus: Das heißt aber, in der Logik drücken nicht wir mit Hilfe der Zeichen aus, was wir wollen, sondern in der Logik sagt die Natur der naturnotwendigen Zeichen selbst aus: Wenn wir die logische Syntax irgendeiner Zeichensprache kennen, dann sind bereits alle Sätze der Logik gegeben.

(Second emphasis mine) [End Page 302]

The first sentence of this passage I take to be an allusion to the second anchor, 3.342:

An unseren Notationen ist zwar etwas willkürlich, aber das ist nicht willkürlich: Dass, wenn wir etwas willkürlich bestimmt haben, dann etwas anderes der Fall sein muss. (Dies hängt von dem Wesen der Notation ab.)

(Third emphasis mine)

It is, I trust, relatively uncontroversial and relatively uninformative to read these passages as saying that in logic only what is “nicht willkürlich” in our notations expresses or asserts, where what is “nicht willkürlich” is characterized in two ways: it is what must be the case once we have arbitrarily (willkürlich) determined something in our notations, and it is “die Natur der naturnotwendigen Zeichen.” As a first step beyond the uncontroversial, I read “willkürlich” here as “up to us,” “up to our arbitrary decision.” That is, in any language there are particular ways of using signs that are open to us to choose. But once having made these choices, there are certain aspects of language that are no longer up to us.19 There are, then, necessary features of language that express or assert themselves in logic. These necessary features constitute logical syntax, and logical syntax is in some sense prior to the propositions of logic.

In order to go any further in understanding these passages, we have to address at least the following questions:

  • • What are the particular ways of using signs that we choose?

  • • What is not arbitrary once these choices are made?

  • • How is the non-arbitrary (connected to) logical syntax?

  • • In what sense is the non-arbitrary in language necessary?

I will begin with a set of answers that I will reject. These can be discerned in Hacker’s conception of logical syntax, advanced in criticism of a striking feature of Diamond and Conant’s interpretation of the Tractatus: in this text Wittgenstein countenances no such things as violations of logical syntax. Central to Hacker’s criticism is the claim that “the rules of logical syntax are constitutive rules” (2000, 366). Hacker’s main example consists in the rules of contract law, which don’t “prohibit something that can be done but should not be done”: “[f]ailure to follow such rules does not result in illegal contracts” (ibid., 365). Rather, “it results in invalid contracts,” which are “not a kind of contract” at all (ibid., 366). In the same way, “if we fail to comply with the rules of logical syntax the result is not the expression of a thought that is illogical (since there is no such thing), but a [sic] nonsense” (ibid., 367). That is to say, the result of non-compliance20 is not the expression of any thought at all; for this reason Hacker takes the rules of logical syntax to determine the bounds of sense (ibid.). Are rules, constitutive of making sense, connected with necessity? There is a familiar answer. One must move the queen in straight paths in chess because otherwise one is not playing chess. So one expects that Hacker would accept a similar view here: one must comply with the rules of logical syntax, otherwise one would not be using language, or not be thinking, at all.21

Hacker discusses just one example of a Tractarian constitutive rule of logical syntax, governing the term ‘object’: [End Page 303]

To use the term ‘object’ as a variable name (formal concept) is correct (for this is the use we have assigned to it), but to use it as a proper concept-word is incorrect—for no meaning has been assigned to it as a concept-word (and to do so would generate undesirable ambiguity).

Once we have assigned a use to the sign ‘object’ as a variable, it will be incorrect to go on to use it in a form of words such as ‘A is an object’ (or ‘A is not an object’), for there it does not occur as a variable but as a genuine name—and no such use has been assigned to the term ‘object’, nor should it be, since the term already has a use.

(2000, 366)

From this example we can gather that for Hacker a rule of logical syntax is or specifies a particular type or category of use of a particular expression. “Type of use” because presumably Hacker doesn’t think that, e.g., it’s a rule of logical syntax that ‘green’ is a predicate correctly applied to green things, so that it would be nonsense, as opposed to plain old false, to say of a red object that it’s green. In the case of ‘object’ the rule of logical syntax specifies that it is to be used as a variable. It is not clear to me what exactly it is to use this word as a variable, but perhaps its use in ‘An object fell’ is a relatively uncontroversial case. Hacker is, in any event, certain that there are uses of this term that are not uses as a variable; for instance, its use in ‘the Earth is an object’ is as a genuine (concept?) name. So evidently “variable” and “proper concept word” or “genuine concept name” are distinct categories of use. (One wonders what Hacker would say about predicating ‘green’ of ideas; is this a type of use of ‘green’ governed by some rule of logical syntax?) In any event non-variable types of uses of ‘object’ don’t comply with the rule of logical syntax governing ‘object’, and so are incorrect in a nonsense-generating way. It seems that, for Hacker, any choice of a particular rule for a use of a sign gives rise to something non-arbitrary: once the choice is made it is not arbitrary what counts as correct and what counts as incorrect types of use of that sign. These non-arbitrary features determine sense and nonsense: incorrect types of use generate nonsense.

Thus the key question for Hacker’s view is: do non-compliant types of uses of signs invariably result in nonsensical pseudo-propositions? Since for Hacker the rules of logical syntax are constitutive of making sense, and, to continue with his example, the logico-syntactic rule governing ‘object’ is that it is to be used as a variable, any failure to comply would have to be nonsense. Here Diamond presses a compelling objection: “when I make a move in language that no one has ever made before, in accordance with no prior rules or stipulations, what I say may be perfectly intelligible and in order; it may be a perfectly good move” (2005, 86). Here is one of her examples of this possibility:

A child is showing off. Someone says ‘He thinks he’s something!’ Suppose that no one has ever used the word ‘something’ in that way before. Suppose (that is) that it has hitherto always been used in ordinary language in a way that goes over to quantifier-with-variable in a formal notation, and that there has never been any other sort of employment of ‘something’. [End Page 304]

What Tractatus 3.326 suggests is that we can recognize the symbol in ‘He thinks he’s something!’, in that we can observe how ‘something’ is used significantly in that proposition and could lay out its use in logically related ones. (We can see that syntactically correct use.)

(Ibid., 83)

More generally, “whatever rules there already are for the use of a word, the word may be given some other employment. Whether anything determinate is being said when it is given that new employment then needs to be looked at in the individual case” (ibid., 86). It seems that Hacker tacitly recognizes this point, for he describes non-compliant uses of ‘object’ as a “concept-word” merely as (in fact) “incorrect— for no meaning has been assigned to [‘object’] as a concept-word.” And he clearly sees that one could assign this word a concept-word use, since he objects that “to do so would generate undesirable ambiguity.” But this amounts to the admission that non-compliance with the supposed logical syntactic rules governing ‘object’ does not invariably result in nonsense. Moreover, if the nonsensicality of sentences is the basis of logical impossibility, then some logical impossibilities might not have to be logically impossible.

I take this objection to be decisive against Hacker’s account of logical syntax as constitutive rules. But it doesn’t rule out discerning in the Tractatus any conception of logical syntax as constitutive of significance. The phrase ‘Regeln der logischen Syntax’ occurs only twice in the Tractatus, in 3.334 and 3.344,22 ‘logischen Syntax’ by itself occurs in merely three other remarks—3.325,23 3.33, and 6.124, and the adjective ‘logisch-syntaktischen’ once in 3.327. Moreover, in none of these texts does Wittgenstein clearly specify examples of rules of logical syntax. Hence it is not mandatory to adopt Hacker’s assumption that they govern or consist in specific types of uses of particular expressions. In the next section I will develop a conception of logical syntax which rejects this assumption. I will observe two constraints. The first is to respect Diamond’s observation, that any word may be used in ways different from established usage without resulting in nonsense. Indeed, I want to add to that observation: as we see in Wittgenstein’s ‘Grün ist grün’ in 3.323, a word may be used ambiguously, in two different ways, within a single meaningful sentence. The second constraint is to make out how logical syntax is nevertheless connected to significance and nonsense. I will also sketch how the conception coheres with the occurrences of ‘logischen Syntax’ in the 3.3s.

IV. COMMITMENTS TO LOGICAL SYNTAX, AUSTERE AND OTHERWISE

The bases of my account are certain implicit commitments of Diamond’s and Conant’s “Frege-Wittgenstein” or “austere” view of nonsense. Their view is developed against two stalking-horses supposedly espousing the “natural” or the “substantial” view of nonsense: Dummett’s reading of Frege’s view of nonsense and Carnap’s criticism of Heidegger. I start with Conant’s account of Dummett. Frege, [End Page 305] according to Dummett, held that the meanings of expressions belong to various logical categories or types. These types determine whether or not the meanings belonging to them can, logically, combine with one another into a proposition or thought; they determine the “logical valency” of these meanings, and, thereby of linguistic expressions that have these meanings. The totality of facts about the logical valencies of meanings determines whether the expressions composing a sentence have meanings that can combine into a proposition or a thought. It thereby determines whether that sentence is meaningful or meaningless, significant or nonsensical. We can then take logical syntax to be descriptions or statements, based on logical valencies, of those combinations of expressions that make up meaningful sentences. A violation of logical syntax would then be a combination of expressions that falsifies these descriptions. Such violations are nonsensical, and their nonsensicality is a result of their being violations of logical syntax.24

Thus Dummett explains why the sentence

(1) Chairman Mao is rare

is meaningless even if grammatically correct as follows. This sentence results from attempting to express the result of combining “the underlined portions of propositions” expressed by

(2) Chairman Mao ate only boiled rice

(3) An honest politician is rare

We attempt to combine the ‘Chairman Mao’ of (2) [the ‘Chairman Mao’ that denotes that individual] and the ‘—is rare’ of (3) [the ‘—is rare’ that denotes that second-level function], and we thus arrive at (1), which . . . is a concrete instance of a special type of meaningless sentence—one that involves a violation of logical category: we have tried to put a proper name into an argument place into which only a first-level function fits. Moreover, what we have here is (alleged to be) a case of fully determinate nonsense: (a) it is logically distinct from other fully determinate cases of substantial nonsense; (b) each of the ‘parts’ of this proposition has a fully determinate sense; and (c) though the sense of the resulting whole is flawed, it is flawed in a determinately specifiable respect . . . : it represents ‘an attempt’ to put that proper name into that argument place for a first-level function. But it will not fit—(in Frege’s words) “the parts cannot logically adhere,” “it makes no sense to fit them together,” “they will not hold together”—thus we get . . . not mere nonsense, but a special variety of nonsense that arises from attempting to do something logically impossible.

(Conant 2002, 397–98)

I pause to register a point that is, by now, familiar.25 This conception of violations of logical syntax does not imply that a meaningless sentence has sense or expresses a thought, only one that is logically flawed. Nothing in the idea of logical valencies implies that the result of combining expressions having incompatible meanings can’t be a sentence that fails to have any sense or express any thought at all. What is crucial to the idea, and crucial to Conant’s subsequent argument, is that it is possible for all the component expressions of substantially meaningless sentences to be meaningful. [End Page 306]

The austere conception of nonsense opposes, against this crucial idea, the claim that if a sentence is meaningless, then at least one, perhaps all, of the expressions that compose it also lack meaning. Part of the case for the austere as against the substantial conception is defensive: one has to remove the main obstacle to accepting the austere conception, the fact that, prima facie, all the words of (1) are words of English with established meanings. So, if (1) is indeed meaningless, it is hard to see that the explanation of its meaninglessness can advert to the meaninglessness of any or all of its component expressions. The argument against this obstacle begins with an observation: the mere fact that (tokens of) a word (type) occur in distinct sentences does not imply that (those occurrences of) that word (type) have the same meaning in those sentences. For example, intuitively, there is a way of understanding the sentence

(4) Trieste is no Vienna

So that the word ‘Vienna’ in this sentence does not mean the same as the word ‘Vienna’ in

(5) Vienna is the capital of Austria

That is, we can take ‘Vienna’ in (4), as Conant suggests, to “mean something like ‘metropolis’ (or perhaps even beautiful or majestic metropolis)” (2002, 399), so that in (4) this word expresses a property that (4) represents Trieste as not having. In contrast, in (5) ‘Vienna’ refers to a city, rather than expresses a property.

This observation can be couched in terms of the distinction between sign and symbol drawn in Tractatus 3.31–3.322. Conant characterizes the distinction thus:

sign  an orthographic unit, that which the perceptible expressions for propositions have in common (a sign design, inscription, icon, grapheme, etc.)

symbol  a logical unit, that which meaningful propositions have in common (i.e., an item belonging to a given logical category: proper name, first-level function, etc.)

(Ibid., 400; emphasis mine)

In these terms, (4) and (5) “have the sign ‘Vienna’ in common [but] have no symbol in common” (ibid., 401).

This observation clearly doesn’t by itself constitute a full response to the obstacle. It tells us no more than that “there will always be room for a question as to whether a given sign, when it occurs in two different sentences of ordinary language, is symbolizing the same way in each of those occurrences” (ibid., 403). But what the austere conception requires is that a sign which symbolizes in some way in one sentential occurrence, e.g., ‘___ is rare’ in (3), fails to symbolize altogether in another sentential occurrence, e.g., ‘___ is rare’ in (1). Are there any such sign occurrences? If there are, what accounts for such divergences in their symbolizing?

The answers to these questions lie in the Tractatus’s version of Frege’s Context Principle. One expression of it is 3.3: “Nur der Satz hat Sinn; nur im Zusammenhang des Satzes hat ein Name Bedeutung.” As Conant reads it, one aspect of this Tractarian [End Page 307] context principle is a view of how we settle the question whether a sign symbolizes in the same way in distinct occurrences, e.g., how do we come to see that ‘Vienna’ in (4) is not the same symbol as ‘Vienna’ in (5)? The view is formulated thus:

Wittgenstein says: “In order to recognize the symbol in the sign we must consider the context of significant use” (§3.326). We must ask ourselves on what occasion we would utter this sentence and what, in that context of use, we would then mean by it. . . . In asking ourselves this, we still rely upon our familiarity with the way words (signs) ordinarily occur (symbolize) in propositions to fashion a segmentation of the propositional sign in question.

(Ibid., 403–4)

One reading of this formulation is that sentence meaning is prior to sub-sentential meaning in the sense that the way a sentence is used in a context, its meaning in that context, determines its division into sub-sentential signs and the ways in which those signs symbolize. Another reading is more overtly epistemic: it is by understanding or making sense of a sentence that we come to see what its (logical) component expressions are and to understand what those components mean. Let’s call the view, in either of these guises, the Tractarian Context Principle, TCP for short. In each case the view opposes the idea that sub-sentential expressions have meanings or can be understood independently of the sentences in which they occur and these independent meanings determine the senses of the sentences in which they occur.

Given the TCP there seems to be a straightforward argument against the substantial conception of nonsense:

To perceive a Satz as sinnvoll is to be able to perceive the propositional symbol in the propositional sign. To perceive a Satz as Unsinn is to be unable to recognize the symbol in the sign. . . . [I]n the case of a piece of nonsense—that is, in the absence of the provision of a context of sinnvollen Gebrauch determining a possible logical segmentation of the Satz—we have no basis upon which to isolate the logical roles played by the working parts of a propositional sign; for, ex hypothesi, there are no working parts of ‘the proposition’.

(Ibid., 404; emphases mine)

It follows then that no meaningless sentence can be composed of meaningful sub-sentential expressions, if such expressions are taken to be signs occurring in that sentence and symbolizing in those occurrences. It also follows that no sentence is an example of a violation of logical syntax in the sense set out above. To be such a violation, a sentence would have to be composed of meaningful expressions whose meanings don’t have the logical valencies that enable them to combine into a proposition. But such a sentence would have no meaning, and so, by the Wittgensteinian view, would not be composed of meaningful expressions. As Conant puts it,

there are no examples of the sort Dummett was looking for—examples of putting a proper name where a concept word belongs—for if one can properly make out that what belongs in that place is a concept word, then that is a sufficient condition for treating whatever is in that place as a concept word. There is not anything . . . that corresponds to [End Page 308] a proposition’s failing to make sense because of the meaning that the parts already have taken in isolation.

(Ibid.)

Let me note in passing that Conant sometimes seems to make a stronger claim: on the Tractarian view of nonsense “we can[not] so much as try to put a logical item into an argument place in which it does not fit” (ibid., 398; emphasis mine).

We are now in a position to see that implicit in this treatment of instances of the priority of sentential to sub-sentential symbolization is a conception of logical valencies of symbols—Tractarian symbols, not signs. These valencies concern what logical segmentations of sentences in use are possible, i.e., what types of sub-sentential symbols can be discerned in meaningful propositions.

It’ll be useful to divide the argument into two steps. The first isolates a crucial assumption in Conant’s view of how, on the TCP, we understand “novel” sentences. Let’s observe, to begin with, that the priority of making sense of a proposition over discerning the (types of) meanings of its component symbols does not imply that we understand sentences as wholes, entirely independently of our understanding of words. Although Conant insists that we begin by asking when we would utter, and what we would mean by, a sentence we are trying to understand, he acknowledges that “we still rely upon our familiarity with the way words (signs) ordinarily occur (symbolize) in propositions to fashion a segmentation of the propositional sign in question.” Indeed, he states in a footnote that

In the absence of any familiarity with the way words (signs) ordinarily occur (symbolize) in propositions, we would have no basis upon which to fashion possible segmentations of propositional signs, and hence no way to recognize . . . the symbol in the sign.

(Ibid., 445, note 84)

What exactly is this “reliance on familiarity with ordinary ways in which words symbolize in propositions”? This becomes clearer if we look at Conant’s account of how we in fact can makes sense of

(1) Chairman Mao is rare,

Dummett’s example of nonsense from violation of logical syntax:

If . . . we attempt to provide a context of significant use for (1), it becomes possible to see the symbol in the sign in ways which Dummett does not consider. There are two equally natural ways to segment this string: (a) to construe ‘Chairman Mao’ as symbolizing a first-level function (on the model of ‘You’re no Jack Kennedy’) [then the sentence might mean something like ‘The kind of exemplary statesmanship Chairman Mao exhibited is rare’], (b) to construe ‘rare’ as symbolizing a first-level function [as in the established English usage ‘That piece of meat is rare!’] These are ‘natural’ ways of ‘reading’ the string because each reading segments the string along lines dictated by an established usage (i.e., an established method of symbolizing by means) of signs. The expression ‘—is rare’ has an established use in the language (in sentences such as ‘An honest politician is rare’) as a second-level function; the expression ‘Chairman Mao’ has an established use in the language (in sentences such as ‘Chairman Mao ate only boiled rice’) as a proper name. Each of [End Page 309] these established uses dictates a possible segmentation of the string—each of which excludes the other. There is not anything that is simultaneously segmenting the string along both lines at once. Segmenting it either way, we supply a possible context of significant use and thus confer upon the string ‘Chairman Mao is rare’ a sense. According to the Tractatus, until we have done this, we have yet to confer any method of symbolizing on any of the signs that make up the string.

(Ibid., 404; emphases mine)

Making sense of sentence (1) in either of these two ways seems to require knowing an “established usage” of some of the component signs of (1). This evidently means knowing the ways those signs symbolize in meaningful sentences. Or, if one wants to avoid the reifying overtones of “ways,” one might put it thus: making sense of (1) requires knowing how these signs symbolize in other meaningful sentences. Thus, the second way of making sense of (1) requires knowing how the words ‘Chairman Mao’ symbolizes in clearly meaningful sentences such as

(2) Chairman Mao ate only boiled rice

Making sense of (1) then proceeds through attempting to understand the sign ‘Chairman Mao’ as it occurs in (1) as symbolizing in the same way as it does in (2).

It is inessential to this account that it’s the very same sign that occurs in the sentence one is trying to understand—call it the “target sentence”—and in sentences one already understands, and equally inessential that the sign occurring in the already understood sentence has a known established use. For example, one might try to make sense of (1) by taking ‘Chairman Mao’ as it occurs in (1) to symbolize in the same way as the sign ‘毛澤東’ symbolizes in

(6) 毛澤東在一九七六年去世

Nor, for that matter, does it seem essential to this account that the established use be what one might call a “conventionally” established use in some natural language. Suppose I use the sign ‘Chairman Mao’ in

(7) Chairman Mao is fond of chasing cats

to describe the behavior of my dog. Nothing, it seems, prevents me from trying to make sense of (1) by hypothesizing that ‘Chairman Mao’ in (1) symbolizes in the same way as that very sign does in sentence (7), as I use that sentence. This last claim is in fact ambiguous. My hypothesis could be that (1) is also about my dog; one might say that in this case that I’m taking these two sign-occurrences to be the same symbol. But I could also suspend judgment over whether (1) is about my dog, or indeed be quite sure that it’s not, and yet hypothesize that just as I use ‘Chairman Mao’ in (7) to describe my dog, so this sign is used in (1) to describe something. Either way, it seems I could thereby succeed in making sense of (1) using just this hypothesis. We could put the point this way: neither partial understanding nor misunderstanding is failure of understanding. So, symbolizing in the same way is implied by but distinct from being the same symbol.26 The upshot of the first step of the argument is that it is crucial, for understanding sentences we have not [End Page 310] encountered before, that there is such a thing as two signs, occurring in distinct sentences, symbolizing in the same way (as opposed to being the same symbol). Call these “co-symbolizing” sign(-occurrence)s.

The second step of the argument establishes the notion of logical valency. The critical point is this: once one adopts a hypothesis about how a component sign of the target sentence symbolizes, the logical segmentation of the target sentence is no longer (fully) up to us. That hypothesis “dictates a possible segmentation of the” target sentence. Thus, once one adopts the hypothesis that the sign ‘Chairman Mao’ in (1) symbolizes in the same way as it does in (2), one cannot take ‘is rare’ in (1) to symbolize in the same way as that very string of letter symbolizes in

(3) An honest politician is rare

That is to say, one cannot take ‘___ is rare’ to function in (1) as a second-level predicate. This is why the two natural segmentations of (1) exclude one another. Of course this exclusion leaves other things open. For instance, it doesn’t prevent one from taking ‘___ is rare’ in (1) to symbolize in the same way as 在一九七六年去世 symbolizes in (6), since that sign functions as a first-level predicate in (6).

It should be fairly clear now in what sense there is a conception of logical valency in the view of the TCP developed by Diamond and Conant. Logical valency in this sense is not a property of meanings, and so of expressions bearing those meanings, that can be possessed independently of the use of sentential signs to express propositions. Logical valency depends, rather, on what logical segmentations of significant sentences are possible. So, for example, proper names have the right logical valency to combine with first-level predicates because, if one discerns or hypothesizes that a part of a sentential sign functions logically as a proper name, then the rest of that sentential sign, which, following Diamond, I’ll call the leftover part (1984, 134), would have to function as a first-level predicate if the entire sentential sign is to make sense. Similarly, proper names don’t have the right logical valency to combine with second-level predicates because, if one discerns or hypothesizes that a part of a sentential sign functions logically as a proper name, then the leftover part of that sentential sign cannot function as a second-level predicate if one is to make sense of the entire sentential sign. Note the direction of explanation. The claim is not that a sentence is meaningful or nonsensical because its component expressions have certain logical valencies specifiable independently of the meaningfulness or the nonsensicality of the sentences in which they occur. It is, rather, because a sentence is meaningful or meaningless when one attempts to take its parts as symbolizing in the same ways as they do in meaningful sentences that expressions symbolizing in these ways have the right or the wrong valencies to combine into a meaningful sentence.

The idea of combinations of symbols allowed by logic is very close to the surface in Diamond’s discussion of the other major stalking-horse of resolution, Carnap’s supposedly nonsensical sentence

(8) Caesar is a prime number [End Page 311]

Diamond spells out how one could turn (8) from nonsense to sense:

Suppose we accept that [(8)] makes no sense, because only of a number can it truly or falsely be said that it is a prime number. In that case it would follow, on the view of nonsense I am explaining, that one kind of Logical Element is: term-for-a-number. That sort of Logical Element can be combined with the predicate of

(9) 53 is a prime number

If ‘Caesar’ is defined as a number term, [(8)] can be regarded as a logical combination of that number term and the predicate term we have in [(9)] understood as it normally is. But unless ‘Caesar’ is defined in such a way, the last four words of [(8)] do not mean what they do in [(9)]; we do not have that numerical predicate, that Logical Element, any more than we have the proper name ‘Parkinson’ in ‘Smith has Parkinson’s disease’.

(1981, 101–2; emphases mine)

Here the idea is that the sign ‘___ is a prime number’, as it occurs in (9), is a particular type of Logical Element, i.e., it symbolizes in a particular way; let’s call this type of Logical Element numerical-predicate. In order for this sign, as it occurs in (8), to be this very Logical Element, i.e., for its occurrence in (8) to co-symbolize with its occurrence in (9), ‘Caesar’ in (8) cannot be the Logical Element that ‘Caesar’ is in

(10) Caesar crossed the Rubicon in 49 BC

as (10) is normally understood. This established usage of ‘Caesar’-in-(10) is as a proper-name-of-a-person Logical Element, so unless ‘Caesar’-in-(8) is given a new (i.e., not usual or established) definition so as to make it a term-for-a-number Logical Element, ‘___ is a prime number’-in-(8) is a different Logical Element from ‘___ is a prime number’-in-(9). That is to say, terms-for-a-number symbols can be combined with numerical-predicate symbols in a meaningful sentence, but proper-name-of-a-person symbols cannot be combined with numerical-predicate symbols in a meaningful sentence. Or rather, to put the point so that its conformity with the TCP is more explicit: in any meaningful sentence in which we can discern a numerical-predicate symbol (logically) combined with another symbol, that other symbol can be a term-for-a-number and cannot be a proper-name-of-a-person. (Clearly the other symbol also could be, e.g., a quantifier Logical Element.)

Just as in the case of (1), there is an alternative to this method of making (8) meaningful. We could take ‘Caesar’-in-(8) to symbolize in the same established way as its occurrence does in (10), i.e., to co-symbolize with ‘Caesar’-in-(10), as a proper name, and define the remainder of (8) so that it could be the kind of symbol that can combine with a personal proper name, for instance, what Diamond calls a “personal predicate.” In either case, however, one has to make a “new assignment of meaning” to make (8) meaningful. At this point Diamond writes,

If we make no such new assignments of meaning, the sentence is simply one which has some superficial resemblance to sentences of two distinct logical patterns; it has a word but no Logical Element in common with some sentences about Caesar, sentences of the pattern: [End Page 312]

(11) proper name of a person combined with personal predicate,

[such as

(10) Caesar crossed the Rubicon in 49 BC]

and it has words but no Logical Element in common with sentences [of the pattern:

term for a number combined with numerical predicate

such as

(12) 53 is a prime number]

It fails to be of . . . pattern [(11)], because a meaning of a certain sort has been determined for ‘is a prime number’; it fails to be of [pattern (12)], because a meaning of a certain sort has not been given to ‘Caesar’. Being of neither pattern (nor of any other), it is nonsense. It is our not having made certain determinations of meaning that we could make that is responsible for its being nonsense.

(Diamond 1981, 102; emphases mine; (11) and (12) my interpolations)

I can now characterize more fully a notion of logical syntax based on the implicit commitments of the austere conception I’ve been making explicit. Logical syntax comprises Diamond’s logical patterns, combinations of ways of symbolizing discernible in meaningful sentences, as well as the impossibilities for sentences to be meaningful through combinations of signs co-symbolizing with their occurrences in meaningful sentences. Logical syntax in this sense, like the logical valencies discussed earlier, is ultimately no more than the possibilities, necessities, and impossibilities in making sense of propositional signs.

On this view the austere conception allows for two kinds of nonsense involving only meaningless signs. There are nonsensical sentences some of whose component signs do not occur in any significant sentence. And there are nonsensical sentences p such that all component signs of p occur in significant sentences, but have no meaning as they occur in p because p cannot exemplify a logically possible pattern if its component signs symbolize in p in the same way that they do in the significant sentences in which they do occur.

That this conception satisfies the two constraints mentioned at the end of the last section is not hard to see. It is consistent with Diamond’s observation, because logical syntax doesn’t dictate any particular type of use of any sign, on pain of nonsense. ‘Something’ can be used intelligibly as a first-level predicate even if hitherto it has always been used as a quantifier phrase. Nor does logical syntax dictate that a sign may not be used in two types of ways in a single sentence, on pain of nonsense: ‘Green is green’ is perfectly intelligible. All that syntax dictates are such things as that there is no significant sentence in which ‘something’ occurs, is used in the same way as ‘He thinks he’s something’, and yet the leftover part of that sentence is also used as a first-level predicate. For instance, ‘Is green is something’ is not intelligible if ‘is something’ is used in the same way as it is used in ‘He thinks he’s something’, and ‘is green’ is used in the same way as it is used in ‘Green is green’. [End Page 313]

That on the present conception logical syntax is connected with sense and nonsense is obvious, and it shows that Hacker’s mistake lies not in the claim that logical syntax is in some way constitutive of making sense, but in looking at the wrong place—specific types of uses of individual expressions—for what is genuinely constitutive of intelligibility. Diamond’s observation exposes this mistake, but note that in the course of making the observation she also claims that “[w]hether anything determinate is being said when [a word with an established use] is given [a] new employment then needs to be looked at in the individual case” (2005, 86). That is, not just any new way of using a sign results in intelligible acts of saying. What, then, if anything, determines whether a new use is intelligible? The present answer is: the patterns of logical syntax. It is these patterns, then, and not types of use of individual expressions, that constitute the bounds of sense.

Let’s now come back to the questions I raised about how to understand 3.342 and 6.124. It is open to us to choose, arbitrarily, to use any sign in any way we want; indeed, nothing prevents us from using signs ambiguously (even if certain confusions may arise more easily if we do). Nothing prevents us from using ‘object’ as a variable, and also or instead as a first-level predicate. What is not up to us, not arbitrary, are the patterns of logical syntax, the ways in which signs symbolize in a meaningful sentence. Thus, once we have chosen to use ‘object’ as a variable, it is no longer up to us whether ‘object’ could be used in this way in a meaningful sentence whose leftover part is used as a proper name. That the leftover part has to comprise a part symbolizing as a quantificational expression and another symbolizing as an incomplete expression, and that the leftover part cannot symbolize as a proper name, are some of the patterns that are logical syntax. These necessities and impossibilities for the symbolizing of signs, given the uses of signs we have arbitrarily settled on, are “die Natur der naturnotwendigen Zeichen” that expresses or asserts itself in our attempts to make meaningful use of sentential signs, determining the successes and failures of those attempts independently of whether we think we have succeeded or failed in making sense.27 Note the necessity of logic, on this conception, is rather different from Hacker’s explanation in terms of constitutive rules. Logical impossibility, on his view, is explained in terms of sentences’ being nonsensical, and nonsense, in turn, is explained in terms of uses of expressions that count as incorrect according to the rules of logical syntax. But on the present view, it should be clear, the modalities of logic are intrinsic to logical syntax since, as noted above, it just consists of the necessities, possibilities, and impossibilities of making sense of propositional signs.

I end this section by showing that this idea of patterns of symbolizing constitutive of significant propositions is implicit also in the work of some critics of Diamond and Conant’s resolute approach, specifically, Sullivan’s (2000) and Proops’s (2001a) account of symbolizing in the Tractatus, based on the passages from Notes on Logic and the Moore Notes:28

Symbols are not what they seem to be. In ‘aRb’, ‘R’ looks like a substantive, but is not one. What symbolizes in ‘aRb’ is that ‘R’ occurs between ‘a’ and ‘b’.

(Wittgenstein 1979, 98) [End Page 314]

[T]he symbol of a property e.g. ψx, is that ψ stands to the left of a name form.

(Ibid., 116).

The reason why, e.g., it seems as if ‘Plato Socrates’ might have a meaning, while ‘Abracadabra Socrates’ will never be suspected to have one, is because we know that ‘Plato’ has one, and do not observe that in order that the whole phrase should have one, what is necessary is not that ‘Plato’ should have one, but that the fact that ‘Plato’ is to the left of a name should.

(Ibid., 116)

I will consider mainly Proops. On his account, in order for a sign to symbolize, facts about its occurrences in sentences have to have significance. Thus the occur-rence of ‘Plato’ in the string ‘Plato Socrates’ fails to symbolize because “the fact that a token of ‘Plato’ occurs to the left of a token of a name” “has not been given meaning” (Proops 2001a, 168). Similarly,

(13) is red is green

is a “nonsense string” because what “symbolizes in ‘predicative’ occurrences of the English expression ‘is green’ is the fact that a token of the sign ‘is green’ stands to the right of a token of a name,” but this string “exemplifies no fact that a token of ‘is green’ occurs to the right of a token of a ‘name’, since, obviously, ‘is red’ is not an English name” (ibid., emphasis mine).

Of course, it isn’t entirely obvious that ‘is red’ is not an English name, since nothing prevents, say, an idiosyncratic landlord from naming her pub (whose exterior is painted green) with just those two words. I doubt that Proops would disagree, and the reason is his account of understanding novel sentences:

When we are presented with a string of phonemes we first have to find the significant facts, if any, and then grasp their significance. This does not mean that understanding a novel sentence is a purely creative act, unconstrained by features of that sentence, for our interpretation of a novel sentence is guided by our recognition of certain familiar signs that crop up again in that sentence. In making sense of a novel sentence we will (tacitly) hypothesize that these signs play host to certain ‘symbolizing facts’ to which we have given meaning in the language. In a nonsense ‘sentence’ this preliminary hypothesis fails: there turn out to be no symbolizing facts in the string. But in a meaningful sentence, once we have recognized the relevant symbolizing facts in the presented string, we will be able to deploy our knowledge of their significance to make sense of the string.

(Ibid., 172)

It is clear that this account, like the Diamond-Conant view, rests on a notion of co-symbolizing. We start, and indeed have to start, with hypotheses that facts about sign-occurrences in the target sentence have the same significance as the same facts about occurrences of the same signs in sentences whose meanings we already understand.29 In the case of ‘is red is green’ our initial hypotheses that ‘is green’ in this sentence symbolizes by occurring to the right of a token of a name fails only because our other initial hypothesis is that ‘is red’ symbolizes in the way it does in sentences we already understand, through the fact it stands to the left [End Page 315] of a name. But we could surely learn, from some locals, say, that in their English idiolect the string ‘is red’ symbolizes in certain sentences through the fact that in those sentences it stands to the left of predicates, and then we would be in a position to understand that sentence as perfectly meaningful. What this shows is that whether “there turns out to be symbolizing facts in the string” depends on whether it is possible for our co-symbolizing hypotheses to fit together. If ‘is green’-in-(13) symbolizes by occurring to the right of a token of a name, then in order for (13) to be meaningful it is impossible for the remaining signs, ‘is red’-in-(13) to symbolize by occurring to the left of a predicate.

The essential involvement of modality in this account of symbolizing is explicit in Wittgenstein’s use of it in the Moore Notes to dissolve Russell’s Paradox. The argument focuses on a sign that is part of the Principia sentence resulting from eliminating all the contextually defined terms from a sentence that purports to state that some class contains itself as a member: φ{ψ!û}. Wittgenstein writes that φ “cannot possibly stand to the left of (or in any other relation to) the symbol of a property. For the symbol of a property, e.g., ψx, is that ψ stands to the left of a name form, and another symbol φ cannot possibly stand to the left of such a fact” (Wittgenstein 1979, 116; second emphasis in original). Now, Proops’s explanation of this argument is, “for the predication ‘φ(ψx)’ to have significance—given the fact . . . that ‘φ’ and ‘ψ!’ symbolize in the same way—there would have to be significance to the fact that the letter ‘φ’ stands immediately to the left of another fact, and of course there are no such facts” (2001a, 171). I take it that Proops is claiming something stronger than: it just happens that there are no such facts. He is surely claiming that there can be no such facts.

V. PROPOSITIONS AS TRUTH-FUNCTIONS AND PATTERNS OF LOGICAL SYNTAX

We have now seen that a view of patterns of symbolizing constitutive of intelligibility of propositions is (largely tacitly) discerned in the Tractatus by resolute interpreters and some of their critics. Is there basis in the Tractatus for connecting this idea to the idea of what is not arbitrary in the symbols we use, explicitly stated in 3.342 and 6.124? In this section I argue that there is. I begin in 5.1 below by tracking down two particularly puzzling sets of remarks in the Tractatus, occurring after 3.342, that link notations with necessity. After outlining the interpretive difficulties they pose, I show, in 5.2, that on the basis of the kind of metaphysical semantics that underlies Hacker’s account of tautology one can make considerable progress on the interpretive difficulties, and formulate an account of logical necessity more satisfying than Hacker’s. However, this account still, like Hacker’s, grounds the necessity of logic on semantic features of propositions that seem to have to be necessary, but whose necessity is unclear. Moreover, in face of the arguments against ascribing commitment to semantic and metaphysical theories to [End Page 316] the Tractatus, it’s worthwhile to see if our interpretive puzzles can be resolved in a different way. In 5.3 and 5.4 I sketch an alternative to the semantic approach. The central idea of this alternative, developed in 5.3 by considering some texts of Frege from a Tractarian perspective, is an account of what it is for a proposition to be a truth-function: it is for two things that are done with propositional-signs— affirming and denying them—to be subject to standards of correctness that fall in specific patterns. These are the patterns of logical syntax; conformity to these patterns is constitutive of the intelligibility of picturing the world with propositions. In 5.4 I complete the sketch of this alternative by arguing, again by drawing on Frege, that the patterns of logical syntax are not facts about how we do or must reason. Moreover, I argue that although, in a sense, they are features of propositions, they are features in which the necessities and impossibilities of logic show forth.

v.1. the non-arbitrary in the tractatus

After the non-arbitrary in notations appears in 3.342, the idea of what is necessary for or in notations is brought up in the 5.47s:

5.474  Die Anzahl der nötigen Grundoperationen hängt nur von unserer Notation ab.

(Final emphasis in original)

5.475  Es kommt nur darauf an, ein Zeichensystem von einer bestimmten Anzahl von Dimensionen—von einer bestimmten mathematischen Mannigfaltigkeit—zu bilden.

(All emphases mine)

5.476  Es ist klar, dass es sich hier nicht um eine Anzahl von Grundbegriffen handelt, die bezeichnet werden müssen, sondern um den Ausdruck einer Regel.

(First emphasis in original)

The relevant background for these remarks is Wittgenstein’s criticism, in 5.451–53, of Russell, for taking logic to have a fixed number of fundamental concepts (Grundbegriffe). Here Wittgenstein claims that logic has to do with fundamental operations (Grundoperationen) rather than concepts, but there is no single privileged (ausgezeichneten) number of fundamental operations; rather, the number of necessary fundamental operations depends on the notation. How the number of fundamental operations depends on the notation is very unclear. 5.475 suggests that associated with each notation is at least one sign-system with a determinate number of dimensions, and that these sign-systems are constructed by fundamental operations. But we are not told whether the number of fundamental operations is the same as the number of dimensions, nor whether the number of dimensions may vary from notation to notation. Now, 5.476 suggests that constructing sign-systems has to do with the expression of a rule. We can perhaps understand what this means in terms of the notion of an operation. The first two remarks in which ‘Operation’ appears are:

4.1273(3)  Wir können das allgemeine Glied der Formenreihe bestimmen, indem wir ihr erstes Glied angeben und die allgemeine [End Page 317] Form der Operation, welche das folgende Glied aus dem vorhergehenden Satz erzeugt.

5.22  Die Operation ist der Ausdruck einer Beziehung zwischen den Strukturen ihres Resultats und ihrer Basen.

This suggests that the sign-systems of 5.475 consists of form-series of signs. The rule or rules for constructing the system produces (erzeugt) (non-initial) signs of the series from preceding signs of the series. These rules are (internal) relations between the structures of these signs. Fundamental operations express these relations.

If we connect these remarks with 3.342, we reach the following view. Settling on a notation is arbitrary. But, once we have done so, it is no longer up to us that (a) there is a system of form-series of signs of the notation with a determinate number of dimensions, (b) this system of signs is constructed by fundamental operations, and (c) these fundamental operations express a rule that relates the structures of members of the form-series.

Some of the things we would like now to know are:

  • • What do these form-series look like?

  • • How are the members of these series structurally related?

  • • What is it to settle on a notation?

  • • What is it for a system of form-series to have the requisite multiplicity?

We can make some headway on these questions by looking at another set of puzzling remarks, 5.512–14:

5.512  “~p” ist wahr, wenn “p” falsch ist. Also in dem wahren Satz “~p” ist “p” ein falscher Satz. Wie kann ihn nun der Strich “~” mit der Wirklichkeit zum Stimmen bringen?

  Das, was in “~p” verneint, ist aber nicht das “~,” sondern dasjenige, was allen Zeichen dieser Notation, welche p verneinen, gemeinsam ist. Also die gemeinsame Regel, nach welcher “~p,” “~~~p,” “~pv~p,” “~p.~p,” etc. etc. (ad inf.) gebildet werden. Und dies Gemeinsame spiegelt die Verneinung wieder.

5.513  Man könnte sagen: Das Gemeinsame aller Symbole, die sowohl p als q bejahen, ist der Satz “p.q.” Das Gemeinsame aller Symbole, die entweder p oder q bejahen, ist der Satz “pvq.”

  Und so kann man sagen: Zwei Sätze sind einander entgegengesetzt, wenn sie nichts miteinander gemein haben, und: Jeder Satz hat nur ein Negativ, weil es nur einen Satz gibt, der ganz außerhalb seiner liegt.

  Es zeigt sich so auch in Russells Notation, dass “q:pv~p” dasselbe sagt wie “q”; dass “pv~p” nichts sagt.

5.514  Ist eine Notation festgelegt, so gibt es in ihr eine Regel, nach der alle p verneinenden Sätze gebildet werden, eine Regel, nach der alle p bejahenden Sätze gebildet werden, eine Regel, nach der alle p oder q bejahenden Sätze gebildet werden, usf. Diese Regeln sind den Symbolen äquivalent und in ihnen spiegelt sich ihr Sinn wieder. [End Page 318]

From 5.514 we see that once a notation is fixed, there are rules for constructing the various classes of propositional-signs mentioned or implied in 5.512–13. So we can take the rule-constructed propositional-signs discussed in these remarks to be members of the form-series of 5.474–76. 5.512(2) actually displays a specific example of a form-series, obviously for a notation which contains the signs ‘~’, ‘v’, and ‘.’:

(14) ~p, ~~~p, ~pv~p, ~p.~p, . . .

5.512 also yields some information about how members of this displayed series are related: they have in common that they deny or reject p. What is clear from 5.513–14 is that there are other form-series in this sign-system: a series of propositional-signs all of which have in common that they affirm p, one whose propositional-signs all affirm p or q, another whose propositional-signs all affirm p and q, “and so forth.” This suggests that the members of each of these unspecified series have in common a single type of affirming or denying. So what is necessary for each notation are fundamental operations for constructing series of signs each of which is characterized by a type of affirmation or rejection.

What is crucial for reaching an interpretation of this view is a construal of what is it for a propositional-sign or symbol to deny or to affirm something. What does it mean to say that, e.g., ‘~p.~p’ denies p? Or for some sign to affirm p or q? Whatever answer we give, we should at least attempt to account for two other striking features of these remarks:

  • • What denies in ‘~p’ is what all the symbols of (14), which all deny p, have in common, rather than the stroke ‘~’,

  • The proposition ‘p.q’ is what all symbols which affirm both p and q have in common.

It’s plausible that there are parallel claims for each of the connectives. E.g.:

  • • What affirms p or q in ‘pvq’ is what all symbols which affirm p or q have in common, rather than the disjunction sign ‘v’,

  • • The proposition ‘~p’ is what all symbols which deny p have in common.

v.2. truth-functions, truth-operations, and the modeling of non-elementary propositions

One approach to solving these puzzles begins from the fact that in 5.513 Wittgenstein claims that ‘q:pv~p’ says the same as ‘q’ and that the tautology ‘pv~p’ says nothing. One might, borrowing an idea with some currency in contemporary philosophy of language, construe that which a proposition “says” semantically, as what it represents, namely, possible states of the world. Recall how this semantic account of propositional representation leads to the claim (TF). Since a proposition is true just in case a possible state of the world it represents is actualized, and since a possible state of the world corresponds to a possible combination of truth and falsity [End Page 319] of elementary propositions, the truth-value of a proposition is a function of the possible truth-values of elementary propositions.

This view of propositional representation is complicated by the notion of truth-operation, and the complication allows us to give an account of the form-series of 5.512–14. The term ‘Wahrheitsoperation’ is introduced at 5.234:

Die Wahrheitsfunktionen der Elementarsätze sind Resultate von Operationen, die die Elementarsätze als Basen haben.

(Ich nenne diese Operationen Wahrheitsoperationen.)

At 5.3(1) it used to give a characterization of propositions different from that of 5:

Alle Sätze sind Resultate von Wahrheitsoperationen mit den Elementarsätzen.

The two characterizations are related in 5.3(2):

Die Wahrheitsoperation ist die Art und Weise, wie aus den Elementarsätzen die Wahrheitsfunktion entsteht.

So truth-functions are formed or constructed from elementary propositions, and truth-operations are the way in which the construction is carried out. That is, while propositions express truth-functions, propositional-signs are constructed from logical operation signs, logical connectives. One might be tempted to think that, e.g., the negation connective ‘~’ expresses the negation truth-function; after all, the proposition ‘~p’ expresses is the negation function of p. But the propositions in the form-series (14) show that the same truth-function of p is expressed by indefinitely many propositions, in whose signs other connectives occur. If each connective expresses a truth-function so that a sign formed from it as the main connective is a truth-function of the propositions connected, then there is no reason to think that the propositions of (14) all express the negation function of p. Moreover, the truth-functional equivalence of ‘~(~p.~q)’ and ‘pvq’ shows that the disjunction sign isn’t required for there to be propositional-signs that are the (inclusive) disjunction function of the propositions p and q; that is to say, in a notation with ‘~’ and ‘.’ but not ‘v’ there are propositional-signs that are the disjunction function of p and q, even though the sign ‘pvq’ is not a propositional-sign of the notation at all. Of course the same point holds of the negation function; in a notation with the Tractarian Sheffer stroke ‘|’ but not ‘~’, ‘~p’ is not a propositional-sign, but the propositional-sign ‘p|p’ is the negation function of p.

Remember that the truth-function of elementary propositions that a proposition is corresponds to the set of possible states of the world that the proposition represents. The complication introduced by truth-operations, then, is that distinct propositional-signs, constructed with different truth-operation signs, nevertheless represent the same possible states of the world, say the same thing. Now, although no particular truth-operation signs are required for the construction of a (propositional-sign that is a) given truth-function, the occurrences of truth-operation signs in, e.g., ‘~(~p.~q)’ and ‘pvq’, play a role in making it the case [End Page 320] that they are the same truth-function of p and q. Consider for example ‘pvq’. The propositions p and q, the bases of this truth-operation, are truth-functions of elementary propositions, i.e., represent sets of possible worlds. The role played by the occurrence of ‘v’ in ‘pvq’ can be characterized in two ways. First, it determines what truth-function of elementary propositions the propositional-sign ‘pvq’ expresses, given the truth-functions expressed by p and by q. ‘v’ thus expresses a function from truth-functions to a truth-function, call such a function a truth-operation-function. Second, the occurrence of ‘v’ determines what set of possible worlds ‘pvq’ represents, given the sets of possible worlds represented by p and by q; on this construal ‘v’ expresses the operation of union on sets of possible states of the world. In general, on the first construal an n-place truth-operation sign σ expresses an n argument truth-operation-function θ such that the truth-function of elementary propositions expressed by the propositional-sign Σ which results from filling the argument-places of σ with propositional-signs π1, . . . , πn is the value of θ for arguments θ1, . . . , θn, where θi is the truth-function of elementary propositions expressed by πi. On the second construal σ expresses an operation Ω from n sets to a set such that the set of possible worlds represented by Σ is the result of applying Ω to the sets of possible worlds represented by π1, . . . , πn.

Assuming that p in the form-series (14) is an elementary proposition, what the members of this series have in common is that they all represent the same possible states of the world, the ones in which p is false. They are the same model of the world, the same symbol; they co-symbolize. Equivalently, they are all the negation function of p: they are true if p is false and vice versa. These possible states of the world, or this truth-function of p also defines what it is for a proposition Q to deny p: it is for Q to represent these possible states, or to be the negation function of p. A proposition that denies p is thus a specific picture of the world, call it a denial-of-p picture. What denies in the sign ‘~p’ is what makes this sign a denial-of-p picture. The occurrence of ‘~’ in this sign doesn’t do the trick, since signs in which ‘~’ doesn’t occur are also denial-of-p pictures. What makes a propositional-sign such a picture is that sign’s expressing the negation function of p. And, the proposition ‘~p’, in accordance with 5.513, is the negation function of p. The picture of the world that is this sign is the same as the picture of the world that all members of (14) are, because they all represent the same possibilities. Obvious analogous characterizations apply to the other form-series of the sign-system. For example, signs which affirm p and q picture possibilities in which p and q are both true, and are the conjunction truth-function of the truth-values of p and q.

We can now give a fuller account of the non-arbitrary in notations. To begin with, whatever it is to settle on a notation, it involves choosing truth-operation signs and the truth-operation-functions they express. A truth-operation-function determines what truth-functions are expressed by propositional-signs in which the truth-operation sign expressing it occurs. Given a choice of truth-operations, there are two things that are not arbitrary. First, it is fixed what truth-functions are expressed by propositional-signs constructible in the notation. So one thing [End Page 321] that is not arbitrary is whether two propositional-signs of the notation are the same truth-function, depict the same possible states of the world. Since the criterion of membership in a form-series is picturing the same thing, it is not arbitrary what distinct form-series of the notation there are. It is a familiar point about the Tractatus that, given the bipolarity of elementary propositions, it follows by combinatorial reasoning (see 4.27 and 4.42) that for n elementary propositions there are 22n distinct truth-functions of these elementary propositions. This fact is not dependent on notation at all. So, second, it is not arbitrary whether, for every possible truth-function or set of possible states of the world, there are propositional-signs of the notation which expresses that truth-function or model those states of the world.

We can also venture a guess that the “determinate number of dimensions” or the “determinate mathematical multiplicity” is the number of distinct possible truth-functions, and so is not notation dependent. What is dependent on notation are the distinct form-series of propositional-signs expressing these truth-functions. So, the necessary fundamental operations of a notation are those required for the expression of all the truth-functions. If there are finitely many elementary propositions, this corresponds to what is now called a minimally adequate set of connectives. For the notations mentioned in the Tractatus the necessary fundamental operations range from just ‘|’ for any notation that contains this truth-operation sign, to notations suggested by the form-series (14), whose fundamental operations are of course either ‘~’ and ‘v’ or ‘~’ and ‘.’, to a notation whose only truth-operation signs are those suggested by 4.442—each possible truth-table schema, with the proposition letters removed, is an operation sign—for which either of the schemata equivalent to the Sheffer stroke is sufficient.

I would like to note three things about the semantic interpretation. First, although it is based on the same metaphysical semantics as Hacker’s reading, it does not characterize the necessity of logic as consisting of the special mode of truth of tautologies. The necessity of logic lies in the impossibility of, e.g., ‘~p’ and ‘~pv~p’ picturing the world differently in the notation of Principia. But the concepts or operations of negation and disjunction are not special: logical necessity lies equally in the impossibility of, say, ‘p|p’ and ‘p|(p|(p|p))’ picturing the world differently in a notation with the Sheffer stroke. No particular set of concepts or propositions captures the necessity of logic. That necessity lies, rather, in all the samenesses and differences of what is pictured by propositions in any adequate notation.

Second, there is no obvious sense in which, by the lights of the semantic construal, logical necessity lies in patterns of symbolizing constitutive of intelligibility. One might say that on this reading it is unintelligible, e.g., that ‘p.q’ and ‘~pv~q’ picture the world differently, but what does this have to do with patterns of symbolizing? This of course is no objection to the semantic interpretation. Since it makes some sense of the 5.47s and 5.51s, perhaps the conclusion we should draw is that there isn’t, after all, any connection in the Tractatus between the conception of logical syntax and necessity sketched in section 4 above and the non-arbitrary in notations. [End Page 322]

Finally, the semantic interpretation seems, at bottom, to be the same kind of view of logical necessity as Hacker’s account. Consider the necessity of ‘p.q’ and ‘~pv~q’ being the same picture of the world. This evidently depends on the very two claims that Hacker’s reading depends on, (BP) and (TF), together with claims about which particular truth-operation-functions are expressed by ‘~’, ‘.’, and ‘v’. If propositions do not represent by being truth-functions, then there seems to be no reason why ‘p.q’ and ‘~pv~q’ might not be different representations of the world. So it seems that the necessity of logic rests on the necessity of the truth-functionality of all propositions. Is (TF) a fact about all propositions? If so, then logical necessity on the semantic construal also rests on metaphysically necessary facts about the semantics of propositions. This raises the same question as we raised about Hacker: why should we think that the fact that all propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions is any more necessary than the fact that all matter is composed of elementary particles?

Moreover, in view of the arguments given by advocates of the resolute approach against taking the Tractatus to be committed to metaphysical and semantical theories, it seems worthwhile to investigate whether there is an alternative to the semantic approach to understanding the 5.47s and the 5.51s.

v.3. affirmation, denial, and patterns of logical syntax

In order to develop the alternative, let’s start with a question about 5.512–14: what significance, if any, is there in Wittgenstein’s switch from the terminology of truth and falsity in the 4s, 5.2s, and 5.3s to the terminology of ‘bejahen’ and ‘verneinen’ in these remarks?

These terms are used as transitive verbs in the text, and, etymologically, they mean saying yes or no to something. An answer to our question lies in the idea of picturing as comparison with facts. Comparison requires or consists in stipulating when the facts are of like sense with the picture and when of opposite sense. These stipulations are connected with saying yes or no to the picture: the facts are of like sense with the picture just in case it is correct to say yes to the picture, to affirm it as in agreement with the facts; and, the facts are of opposite sense with the picture just in case it is correct to say no to the picture, to deny or reject it as out of agreement with the facts. Thus picturing is not separable from establishing standards of correctness governing these two central acts that can performed with pictures.

How, though, is this characterization of affirmation and denial related to truth and falsity? Let’s consider 4.431. After equating a proposition’s expressing agreement and disagreement with truth-possibilities with that proposition’s expressing its truth conditions, Wittgenstein writes parenthetically, “Frege hat sie daher ganz richtig als Erklärung der Zeichen seiner Begriffsschrift vorausgeschickt” (4.431(3)). The pronoun ‘sie’ surely refers to the proposition’s truth conditions, mentioned in the previous sentence (4.431(2)). So the question is, where and how does Frege give explanations of signs of his Begriffsschrift by giving truth conditions? Frege sets out somewhat different accounts of the primitive signs of Begriffsschrift in [End Page 323] Begriffsschrift and in volume 1 of Grundgesetze (1893). One main difference is that in Grundgesetze truth and falsity are taken to be objects that are both the arguments and the values of the functions named by the primitive signs corresponding to sentential connectives. Now, Wittgenstein continues the parenthetical note cited above thus: “Nur ist die Erklärung des Wahrheitsbegriffes bei Frege falsch: Wären ‘das Wahre’ und ‘das Falsche’ wirklich Gegenstände und die Argumente in ~p etc., dann wäre nach Freges Bestimmung der Sinn von ‘~p’ keineswegs bestimmt.” This suggests that we should focus on the Begriffsschrift accounts. Part I of that book is titled “Erklärung der Bezeichnungen,” and the third sign explained, after the judgment and content strokes, is the sign of conditionality (Bedingtheit):

§5. Wenn A und B beurtheilbare Inhalte bedeuten, so giebt es folgende vier Möglichkeiten:

  1. 1. A wird bejaht und B wird bejaht;

  2. 2. A wird bejaht und B wird verneint;

  3. 3. A wird verneint und B wird bejaht;

  4. 4. A wird verneint und B wird verneint.

  ⊦ BA

bedeutet nun das Urtheil, dass die dritte dieser Möglichkeiten nicht stattfinde, sondern eine der drei andern. Wenn

  – BA

verneint wird, so besagt dies demnach, dass die dritte Möglichkeit stattfinde, dass also A verneint und B bejaht werde.

(Frege 1879, 5; notation updated)

There are three striking points about this text. First, Frege doesn’t mention truth or falsity or truth conditions at all. Second, Frege uses precisely the verbs ‘bejahen’ and ‘verneinen’ of the 5.51s, but note that he uses them in the passive voice. Finally, Frege’s explanation proceeds in terms of possibilities of being affirmed and being denied. Now at first glance the explanation comes in two parts somewhat different in form. The first part tells us what judgment is meant (bedeutet) by a sign that results from prefixing the sign constructed by joining A and B with the condition stroke—‘BA’—with the judgment and content strokes. The second part tells us what is meant when the content of this sign is denied. But the vertical judgment stroke expresses the affirmation (Bejahung) of the judgeable content bound together by the content stroke.30 So the two parts of the explanation are parallel: the first specifies the affirmation and the second the denial of the conditional content. Now, what is the significance of Frege’s use of the passive voice? Since Frege is here introducing a new sign, it makes no clear sense to think that he is describing how people did affirm or deny signs of the form ‘—BA’, or predicting how they will, or drawing the consequences of supposing that they do. It makes better sense to read this passage as stipulating when it is correct to affirm or deny this new sign. That is, it is a stipulation, given arbitrary propositions A and B, of the conditions under which the (content of the) sign constructed by joining A and B with the condition stroke, – B → A, is correctly judged, i.e., affirmed, and of the conditions under which it is correctly denied, where each condition consists of [End Page 324] one of the four possible combinations of correctly affirming and denying A and B taking place (stattfinde).

Consider now two well-known and perplexing aspects of Frege’s views of truth and judgment. First, truth is a or the aim of judgment; there is no such thing as judging that does not aim at judging true thoughts. Second, although judgment is acknowledgment of the truth of a thought, this is not an analysis of judgment in terms of an independent conception of truth as a property of thoughts or an object to which thoughts are related.31 These points suggest that treating truth conditions as affirmation conditions means also that giving truth conditions for propositional-signs is the same thing as specifying conditions for judging contents or thoughts they express, i.e., conditions for affirming them. These conditions are normative; they lay out how correct affirmation or judgment is to be carried out. Thus, the terminology of affirmation and denial is not quite a mere variant of the terminology of truth and falsity. Rather, it indicates a particular conception of truth and falsity, as essentially connected with norms governing two central actions effected with propositions.

Given this view of truth and falsity, we can formulate a conception of what it is for propositions to be truth-functions. Suppose a propositional-sign S is constructed from truth-operation signs and other propositional-signs S1, . . . Sn. That the proposition expressed by S is a truth-function of those expressed by S1, . . . Sn means that the conditions of (correct) affirmation and denial of S are specified in terms of combinations of (correct) affirmation and denial of S1, . . . Sn.

One doubt about ascribing this conception of truth-functions to the Tractatus comes from the fact that according to 5 propositions are truth-functions of elementary propositions. But obviously elementary propositions play no role in Frege’s explanation; the affirmation and denial conditions are given for conditional propositions whose antecedent and consequent are arbitrary propositions. But in fact we can discern this conception in the Tractatus by considering 5.31:

Die Schemata No. 4.31 haben auch dann eine Bedeutung, wenn ‘p’, ‘q’, ‘r’, etc. nicht Elementarsätze sind.

Und es ist leicht zu sehen, dass das Satzzeichen in No. 4.442, auch wenn ‘p’ und ‘q’ Wahrheitsfunktionen von Elementarsätzen sind, eine Wahrheitsfunktion von Elementarsätzen ausdrückt.

(Emphasis mine)

The three schemata in 4.31 are presentations in truth-tables of the truth-possibilities of one, two, and three elementary propositions. Thus, if the letters occurring in these schemata stand for arbitrary non-elementary propositions, then the meaning (Bedeutung) that they would have is as presentations of the truth-possibilities of these propositions. The propositional-sign in 4.442 is the truth-table for nothing other than the conditional sign. In that remark, after displaying this propositional-sign, Wittgenstein goes on to say,

Ist die Reihenfolge der Wahrheitsmöglichkeiten im Schema durch eine Kombinationsregel ein für allemal festgesetzt, dann ist die letzte Kolonne allein schon ein Ausdruck der Wahrheitsbedingungen. [End Page 325]

Thus, if ‘p’ and ‘q’ in this propositional-sign stand for arbitrary non-elementary propositions, then the schema expresses the truth conditions of this (conditional) propositional-sign, constructed from the signs p and q, in terms of agreement and disagreement with truth-possibilities, not of elementary propositions, but of the propositions p and q. Given the hypothesis that an explanation of truth conditions is an explanation of affirmation and denial conditions, I take it that for Wittgenstein these (schematic) specifications of agreement and disagreement with truth-possibilities of possibly non-elementary propositions are explanations of affirmation and denial conditions.

On this conception of truth-functions as affirmation functions, the conclusions we reached about 5.512–14 would be understood somewhat differently. A propositional-sign S affirms p or q just in case S is to be affirmed under the same conditions as ‘pvq’ is, and to be denied under the same conditions as ‘pvq’ is. But ‘pvq’ has no privileged place as far as these affirmation and denial conditions are concerned; they are what all the propositions in the form-series containing ‘pvq’ have in common, and of course propositions in notations without the disjunction sign can have these conditions as well. So what affirms p or q in the sign ‘pvq’ is not the disjunction sign ‘v’ occurring therein but the whole sign ‘pvq’ as having these conditions of affirmation and denial. The identification of a proposition with what is common to all the symbols of the form-series now means that the proposition ‘pvqis this set of affirmation and denial conditions. We can think of it this way: the proposition that a propositional-sign expresses are norms of affirming and denying that sign, so if two propositional-signs are governed by the same norms of affirmation and denial, then they express the same proposition.

The distinction between truth-function and truth-operation now appears as the claim that although each truth-operation sign is explained in terms of the correct affirmation and denial of propositional-signs constructed using that sign, two propositional-signs could be constructed from entirely different truth-operation signs and yet are correctly affirmed or denied in the same circumstances. This means that these propositional-signs are one and the same proposition. Thus, the occurrence of any operation(-signs) in a propositional-sign S does not characterize the sense of the proposition that S expresses because exactly the same norms of affirmation and denial that govern S also govern propositional-signs in which those operation signs do not occur.32

Taking propositions to be affirmation functions leads to a view of patterns of propositional symbolizing. What is it to specify the conditions of correct affirmation of ‘pq’ as a function of the correct affirmation of p and of q? It is to specify, e.g., that ‘pq’ is correctly denied if p is correctly affirmed and q correctly denied, and that ‘pq’ is correctly affirmed if p is correctly denied and q correctly denied, and so on. What this amounts to is that the standards of correctness governing the affirmation and denial of these three propositional-signs fall into certain patterns. Now, the same pattern of norms governs the affirmation and denial of ‘~(p.~q)’, p, and q, of ‘~pvq’, p, and q, and so on. That is, the same pattern governs the affirmation [End Page 326] and denial of p, q, and any member of the series of propositional-signs that affirms p only if q. Moreover, this shows that the same patterns of norms governing affirmation and denial of propositions could occur both within and across notations. For instance, the pattern governing ‘pq’, p and q in a notation containing ‘⊃’ is the same as the pattern governing ‘~(p.~q)’, p, and q in a notation that doesn’t contain ‘⊃’ at all.

These patterns are rules or patterns of logical syntax. What is arbitrary in a notation consists, as under the semantic interpretation, of the choices of truth-operations. What is not arbitrary consists of the patterns of norms governing the affirmation and denial of propositional-signs constructed with truth-operations and of the base propositional-signs. Thus it is up to us to choose truth-operations, e.g., ‘~’, ‘.’, and ‘v’. But once having adopted these operations, it is no longer up to us, e.g., that each of ‘~(p.~q)’ and ‘~pvq’ is correctly affirmed if p is correctly denied and q correctly affirmed. Just as, although nothing prevents us from using ‘object’ as a first-level predicate, once we’ve made that choice it is no longer up to us that in a significant sentence in which ‘object’ is used in this way the remainder of the sentence has to be used, e.g., as a proper name, or as a quantifier phrase. Recall that, in that case, “it is not up to us” means that it is unintelligible for a sentence to contain ‘object’, used in the first-level predicate way, but for the remainder of the sentence to be also used in the first-level predicate way. In the present case it is unintelligible for ‘pq’ to be correctly affirmed when p is correctly affirmed and q correctly denied. In this sense these patterns of norms governing affirmation and denial are constitutive of the intelligibility of propositions expressed by signs constructed using the conditional truth-operation sign. More generally, what is not arbitrary in a notation or in the symbols we use are the pattern of norms governing affirmation and denial that are invariant within and across notations.

I would like to note in passing that with this conception of the non-arbitrary we can sketch an objection to Frege’s and Russell’s conceptions of logic that does not rest on Hacker’s misunderstanding of their views. Consider 5.42(2): “Die Möglichkeit des kreuzweisen Definierens der logischen ‘Urzeichen’ Freges und Russells zeigt schon, dass diese keine Urzeichen sind.” Wittgenstein’s criticism is based on the fact that both Frege and Russell are quite aware that the particular propositions, involving the particular functions, that they adopted as basic laws are not the only possible ones; other functions could be taken as primitive, other propositions adopted. So the question is, what makes these particular propositions the ones according to which all inference is to take place? Given the acknowledged existence of alternatives, isn’t it arbitrary to adopt these propositions? If it is arbitrary, then how could one take this adoption to be based on the identification of the universal standards of correctness in reasoning?33 This worry would remain even if Frege and Russell had accepted that the propositions of logic are not substantive general truths but empty tautologies, provided that they still identified some particular selection of tautologies as the primitive propositions of logic and regarded the remaining propositions of logic as derived from, and so based on, [End Page 327] these ausgezeichneten tautologies. The point of course is that for Wittgenstein it’s the system for constructing truth-functions by truth-operations in each notation that is logically important, not any particular set of truth-operations. One might put it this way: from Wittgenstein’s perspective, Frege and Russell fetishized their notations, their Begriffsschriften, taking them to be logically essential and thereby mistaking what is genuinely logically essential, namely, what all adequate notations have in common.34 For Wittgenstein no notation, no Begriffsschrift, should be taken to have captured the essence of the logical, in preference to any other adequate Begriffsschrift.35

v.4. anti-psychologism and our attitude to logic

But what does all this talk of patterns of norms constitutive of intelligibility amount to? Is it a description of how we reason, what judgments we take to be correct? Or is it a description of facts about propositions? To complete the sketch of our alternative to the semantic reading, I now turn to show, by examining Frege’s well-known criticism of psychologism in logic, how the patterns of logical syntax need not be taken to be facts about how we do or must think. I will also suggest that while in a sense logical syntax consists of facts about propositions, to see them as other than facts about us is also to see them as facts intrinsically involving the necessity of logic.

Psychological logicians hold that the laws of logic are descriptions of how we think. Frege starts his polemic by pointing to an implication of this view, that there could be “logical aliens,”36 “Wesen . . . deren Denkgesetze den unsern geradezu widersprächen” (1893, xvii) Frege continues,

Der psychologische Logiker könnte das nur einfach anerkennen und sagen: Bei denen gelten jene Gesetze, bei uns diese. Ich würde sagen: Da haben wir eine bisher unbekannte Art der Verrücktheit. . . .

Aus der Logik heraustretend kann man sagen: wir sind durch unsere Natur und die äussern Umstände zum Urtheilen genöthigt, und wenn wir urtheilen, können wir dieses Gesetz—der Identität z.B.—nicht verwerfen, wir müssen es anerkennen, wenn wir nicht unser Denken in Verwirrung bringen und zuletzt auf jedes Urtheil verzichten wollen. Ich will diese Meinung weder bestreiten noch bestätigen und nur bemerken, dass wir hier keine logische Folgerung haben. Nicht ein Grund des Wahrseins wird angegeben, sondern unseres Fürwahrhaltens. Und ferner: diese Unmöglichkeit, die für uns besteht, das Gesetz zu verwerfen, hindert uns zwar nicht, Wesen anzunehmen, die es verwerfen; aber sie hindert uns, anzunehmen, dass jene Wesen darin Recht haben; sie hindert uns auch, daran zu zweifeln, ob wir oder jene Recht haben. Wenigstens gilt das von mir. Wenn Andere es wagen, in einem Athem ein Gesetz anzuerkennen und es zu bezweifeln, so erscheint mir das als ein Versuch, aus der eignen Haut zu fahren, vor dem ich nur dringend warnen kann.

(Ibid., xvii–xviii [14–15]; emphasis mine)

On the basis of the first paragraph quoted it is tempting to think that according to Frege the aliens are not thinking at all, for they exhibit “a hitherto unknown type of madness.” So there is no such thing as thinking without acknowledging the laws of [End Page 328] logic. The second paragraph, however, shows that this isn’t quite right. There Frege rejects the claim that we must acknowledge a law of logic because otherwise our thoughts are brought to confusion and we can’t make judgments any more. The problem with this claim is that the ground cited for the necessity of acknowledging logical laws is merely a psychological fact about our thinking, with no implications for the thinking of the logical aliens. We can consistently accept that we can’t think if we reject the law of identity, and yet also suppose that others can. This shows that Frege does not insist that the aliens do not think at all, however mad they might be. It is, then, perfectly possible to reject a logical law and yet think. What we cannot suppose, according to Frege, is that the aliens are thinking correctly. I take Frege here to be characterizing the concept of acknowledging a law of logic, spelling out what it is to acknowledge something as such a law: to do so is to find it unintelligible that there is thought that correctly rejects the law.37 The incorrectness of rejecting that thought is a necessary condition for thinking at all, and so partially constitutes what it is to think. To put it in a slogan: Frege here lays out some normative consequences, for the constitution of thought, of acknowledging a law of logic.

Let’s consider now how these normative consequences figure in the rejection of psychological logic. From Frege’s perspective, the psychological logician, PL, thinks of a law of logic, L, in two ways. On the one hand, PL claims to acknowledge L (the thought it expresses) as true, adding that we all do. But, on the other hand, PL sees this acknowledgment as a fact about our psychological makeup; we can’t do otherwise, and so our acknowledgment of it is right for us. But others, with different psychologies, can, and their rejection of L is right for them. Frege sees nothing wrong with the actual and possible facts PL adduces: we can’t help but acknowledge L, but it is conceivable that others can. The problem that Frege sees is PL’s view that rejection of L is correct for those others. Frege would ask PL: do you really acknowledge L as a law of logic? And if you do, do you really find it intelligible that these others are right? The problem is not, or not only, that PL fails to grasp the concept of acknowledging a law of logic. It is that PL is trying to acknowledge L and at the same time to consider that acknowledgment as a mere fact about us. Taking the acknowledgment to be a fact is taking it to have no normative consequences, and so conflicts with his acknowledgment of L. This is, in Frege’s colorful phrase, “ein Versuch, aus der eignen Haut zu fahren.” PL dithers, to use Diamond’s term (1997, 78), between two perspectives: the perspective of an observer of facts about us, about how we treat L, and the perspective of acknowledging L, embracing its normative consequences. Thus, the plight of PL shows that acknowledging L and thereby being committed to its correctness as a necessary condition for thought is incompatible with treating that acknowledgment as a fact about certain thinkers. I should perhaps emphasize that this is not to claim that treating the acknowledgment as such a fact is impossible or illegitimate; it is merely to claim a conflict between this perspective and the perspective of acknowledging a logical law.

Wittgenstein, I hold, accepts the fundamental shape of Frege’s anti-psychologism: taking a certain attitude toward logic, which in Frege is acknowledging certain [End Page 329] thoughts as true, has normative consequences for the constitution of thought, and is incompatible with seeing the taking of this attitude to be a fact about us, about how we think or must think. He rejects, however, Frege’s conception of taking that attitude to logic as acknowledging the truth of those particular thoughts that are the laws of logic. What for Wittgenstein replaces acknowledging the truth of a logical law is taking a proposition to be an affirmation function of its bases. To see what this amounts to, consider again the affirmation function Frege stipulates for propositional-signs constructed with the conditional operation sign. To accept this stipulation is to take conditional propositions to be affirmation functions of their bases. And to do this is, e.g., to take it to be incorrect to affirm ‘pq’ when it is correct to affirm p and incorrect to affirm q, to take it to be correct to affirm this sign when it is correct to deny p and to affirm q, and so on. It is to take the correctness and incorrectness of the affirmation and denial of conditional propositional-signs and their bases to exemplify the patterns of the affirmation functions Frege specifies. Now, for Frege the consequence of acknowledging a law of logic is to make it impossible to suppose that there is such a thing as thinking correctly in rejecting that law. In Wittgenstein’s case the consequences of, e.g., taking conditional propositions to be affirmation functions of their bases is to make it impossible to suppose, e.g., that there is such a thing as thinking or picturing the world with conditional propositions in which it is right to affirm ‘pq’ when it is right to affirm p and wrong to affirm q, or that it is right to deny ‘pq’ when it is right to affirm both p and q, and so on. More generally, taking a proposition to be an affirmation function of a set of base propositions makes it impossible to suppose that there is such a thing as thinking with those propositions that does not conform to the patterns of assessment of logical syntax. It is in this way that the patterns of logical syntax are constitutive of intelligibility: they are so in virtue of our taking the correctness and incorrectness of affirmation and denial of propositions to be governed by logical syntax. And so it is in treating propositions in this way that the necessity of logic lies. In contrast to Frege, for Wittgenstein the norms of logic do not govern merely the correctness of affirming certain special thoughts, but pervades the activity of thinking by picturing the world with propositions. However, like Frege, Wittgenstein holds that the perspective of acknowledging logic, i.e., taking the patterns of logical syntax as governing all thought, is incompatible with the perspective of treating the taking of this attitude as facts about how we think or picture the world.

Now, what about the other suggestion, that the patterns of norms of logical syntax are facts about propositions? One can take this in two ways. First, the patterns are grounded on semantic facts. For example: it is correct to affirm ‘pvq’ if it is correct to affirm p because it is correct to affirm a proposition if it is true and a proposition is true if one of the sets of possible worlds it represents is actual and ‘pvq’ represents the union of the sets of possible worlds represented by p and by q. The normative interpretation I’m sketching is meant to respect the scruples of the resolute approach about ascribing a metaphysical semantics to the Tractatus. So it’s [End Page 330] part of this interpretation to hold that there is no independent semantic explanation of the patterns of norms that we take to govern proposition affirmation.

The other way to take the suggestion is this: that propositional affirmation is governed by these patterns of norms is a property or feature of propositions; it is a general fact about propositions that they have these features. As mentioned above, I think this is right. However, I want to point to the kind of fact or feature of propositions that such a pattern of norms is.

Let’s consider again the claim that ‘p.q’ and ‘~pv~q’ are necessarily the same picture of the world. If we ask why this is so, the answer, on the semantic interpretation, is based on semantic facts about what propositions of these forms represent. One of these is:

‘p.q’ represents the intersection of the sets of possible worlds represented by p and by q

What corresponds to this semantic fact on the normative interpretation? It is surely that

‘p.q’ is correctly affirmed just in case p and q both are.

This is the specification of an affirmation function, of a pattern of norms governing the affirmation of three propositional-signs. What we saw from the rejection of psychologism is that, from the perspective of taking ‘p.q’ to be this particular affirmation function of p and q, it is unintelligible that the correctness and incorrectness of the affirmation and denial of these three propositions fails to exemplify this pattern. This is to say that it is impossible for the affirmation of ‘p.q’ to be correct, except when the affirmation of p and q both also are. Thus, if it is a fact about propositions of the form ‘p.q’ that the correctness of its affirmation conforms to this pattern of logical syntax, then, from the perspective from which this fact is visible, the perspective of acknowledging this pattern of logical syntax, this fact appears as intrinsically involving certain impossibilities and necessities. That is to say, from this perspective the modalities of logic show forth.

Sanford Shieh
Wesleyan University

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

I would not have come to write this paper if Arata Hamawaki had not persuaded me to participate in the marvelous conference on the Tractatus that he and Kelly Jolley organized at Auburn University; I thank them both for their hospitality. At Auburn and subsequently I benefited from discussions with Jean-Philippe Narboux on connections between my ideas and his views on the notion of showing forth in the Tractatus. Reactions to my talk at Auburn by Peter Sullivan, Jim Conant, Cora Diamond, and Tom Ricketts showed me just how much my earlier ideas lacked engagement with the Tractatus itself; I hope to have done a bit better here. I have given parts of the paper in a seminar at Boston University and at the [End Page 331] SSHAP conference at Indiana University; I would like to thank the audiences at both occasions. At SSHAP in particular I had very useful discussions with Gary Ebbs and Tom Ricketts, although, alas, I have not been able to do very much here to address their worries. Thanks to Max Weiss, who has kindly given me detailed comments on an earlier draft. Finally, every idea in this paper has been influenced by innumerable discussions with Juliet Floyd; I am endlessly grateful to her for her insights and encouragement.

NOTES

1. For me this question is closely connected with another: are the Tractatus’s criticisms of Frege’s and Russell’s views of logic connected with its stance on logic and necessity? I will in this essay say nothing very substantial or systematic on this other question.

2. The Tractatus is cited by remark number from Wittgenstein (1921; 1989).

3. Tom Ricketts suggested to me looking for a conception of logical necessity in the Tractatus in 6.124 and its companion, 3.342. Naturally the conception that I outline here may well be nothing like what he has mind.

4. I take the notion of “showing forth” from Jean-Philippe Narboux (unpublished), although he should not be taken to endorse my uses of it.

5. One might see, in Russell’s remark in Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy that “logic is concerned with the real world just as truly as zoology, though with its more abstract and general features” (1919, 169) a line of argument from maximal generality to necessary presence in the world. We attain the logical constants by a process of abstracting from specific entities occurring in true propositions. In this way the constants refer to structures present in all worldly facts, no matter what particular entities they involve. So those structures are common to all possible worlds. Since these structures are common to all possible worlds, the conditions for the truth of descriptions of them are fulfilled in all possible worlds if they are fulfilled in any.

6. Or a different maximally abstract structure. If Hacker is moved by this sort of intuition, he has company. Joseph Almog, for one, used to hold that since logical truths depict structural features of the world, they don’t have to be necessary; see (1989).

7. In more detail, Russell starts by explaining the notion of “analytic proposition” in terms of the relation called “deducibility,” where “q is deducible from p if it can be shown by means of the [axioms of logic] that p implies q” (1994, 520); i.e. if there exists a derivation of the proposition (expressed by) “p implies q” from the axioms of logic. A proposition is analytic if it is deducible from the axioms of logic. Given this account, Russell says, “[i]t is now open to us, if we choose, to say that a necessary proposition is an analytic proposition, and a possible proposition is one of which the contradictory is not analytic” (ibid., 517).

Note that this attitude to modality is consistent with what we find in Russell’s Theory of Knowledge manuscript, a work with which Wittgenstein may well have been familiar: “The notion of what is ‘logically possible’ is not an ultimate one, and must be reduced to something that is actual before our analysis can be complete” (1984, 111).

8. One might think that Russell held this anti-modal view only around the time of Principles, since, in Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, he writes, “[p]ure logic aims at being true, in Leibnizian phraseology, in all possible worlds” (1919, 192). Russell certainly did change his mind on a number of issues over the course of the first two decades of the last century, but I don’t think the relation of logic and modality is one of them. Rather, Russell would take the remark about logic and possible worlds in his prison document to be explicable, ultimately, in terms of one of his reconstructions of the notion of possibility.

9. Frege’s immediate target in Begriffsschrift §4 is Kant’s Table of Judgments in Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1787, §9, A70/B95). Frege’s rejection of Kant’s characterizations of judgments under the [End Page 332] titles of Quantity, Quality, and Relation is thoroughgoing. However, although he doesn’t hold that there is a difference in content between apodeictic and assertoric judgment, his characterization of the differences between these judgments is not that far from Kant’s.

10. In the case of Frege this point requires some qualification. Although modal predicates don’t contribute to conceptual content and modal assertions are analyzed in terms of inferential relations between those assertions and others, Frege does sometimes characterize logical features of judgments in modal terms. For a central instance, in criticism of Kerry Frege writes, “Ich will nicht sagen, es sei falsch, das von einem Gegenstande auszusagen, was hier von einem Begriffe ausgesagt wird; sondern ich will sagen, es sei unmöglich, es sei sinnlos”(1967a, 174; op. 200).

11. Unlike Hacker, Gordon Baker (1988) grasped Frege’s modal reductionism in logic; but, since in his view such reductionism is insane, he took it as yet another strike against the philosophical value of Frege’s thought. I would like to note, contra Baker, that a view of logic as completely general truths on the basis of which modal notions are explicable is in some ways more robust than a view of logic as intrinsically modal. For example, consider the following argument against the coherence of the very idea of logical laws. Logical laws have to be necessarily true, but what is a necessary truth? Surely it’s a truth whose falsity is not conceivable. But, equally surely, we understand the propositions stating these logical laws. So we must understand their negations as well. But then how could the falsity of these propositions not be conceivable? The argument would not go through if inconceivability is taken to be explained in more fundamental logical terms, for instance, a proposition p is inconceivable if a contradiction is deducible from it. “Deducible” here does not express a modal notion. A contradiction is deducible from p, if there exists a proposition of the form ‘q and not-q’ such that there exists a derivation of the implication ‘p implies q and not-q’ from the axioms of logic. Of course an inconceivable proposition, on this explanation, is one we can understand and even believe, but what’s wrong with that? It’s a problem only if one is working with imprecise, “folk,” notions of conceivability.

12. Indeed, someone might take the Wittgenstein’s greatness as a philosopher to be more or less a guarantee that his criticisms of his great predecessors would rest on misapprehension of their views. (Of course we all know who that someone is: my teacher Burton Dreben.)

13. I’m indebted to Max Weiss for discussion leading this formulation of the difficulty facing Hacker’s view.

14. I’m taking a bit of interpretive license here. First, I take Diamond to be referring to elementary sentences when she mentions “sentences [that] can be seen directly to have the . . . possibility of comparison to reality . . . which yields true or false . . . independent of the truth value of any sentence” (1988, 193). Second, I take her to be alluding to N in speaking of “a method of construction . . . such that if the base sentences have seeably got the logical characteristic of sentences, the results will be sentences seeably sharing the characteristic or will seeably be merely sentence-like constructions never comparable with reality” (ibid.)

15. I’m indebted to Jean-Philippe Narboux for this point.

17. Dummett (1981) was perhaps the first to ascribe these logico-syntactic criteria for being a proper name to Frege. Dummett also argues that these first-order forms of inference are not sufficient to isolate proper names; see also Hale (1987) for further refinements of these criteria in terms of higher-order forms of inference.

18. One interesting point to note about Geach’s logic of duality is that tautologies and contradictions are not self-dual—indeed, the dual of each tautology is a contradiction in the original language, and vice versa. So it would seem that they pass the criterion of logical propositionhood.

19. I take this terminology of what is not or is not “up to us” from Diamond: “[i]t is not up to us to choose whether we shall have a language in which whenever there is a function-expression it will be incomplete” (1988, 182).

20. I will follow Hacker in using the term ‘compliance’ in discussing his notion of constitutive rules, since it “is misleading to speak of ‘violating’ the rules of contract formation and equally misleading to speak of ‘violating’ the rules of logical syntax. One should confine oneself to speaking of failing to comply with them, of failing to follow or observe them” (ibid., 365–7).

21. So far as I can see, though, in his criticism of Diamond and Conant, Hacker appears to take a different line. He explicitly rejects one connection with necessity and suggests that he holds [End Page 333] another. Since non-compliance with logical syntax results in nonsense, words that do not depict any situation, it does not, a fortiori, result in descriptions of any logically or metaphysically impossible situations. So the connection is not that one gets from non-compliance descriptions of “logical . . . or . . . metaphysical impossibilit[ies]” (Hacker 2000, 367). But Hacker characterizes what Wittgenstein takes to be the problem raised by impossibility proofs in mathematics thus: “if the trisection of an angle is logically impossible (i.e., if the form of words ‘trisecting an angle with compass and rule’ lacks sense), how could mathematicians have raised the question of the possibility of trisecting an angle?” (Hacker 2003, 14; second set of emphases mine). This suggests that his view is that what appears to be an ascription of logical impossibility to a state of affairs (‘the trisection of an angle is logically impossible’) is in fact a (meta-linguistic) claim of nonsensicality.

This suggests that Hacker has two accounts of logical impossibility. The one we’ve been discussing derives from nonsense generating non-compliance with logical syntax. The other consists in the mode of falsity of contradictions.

22. Occurrences of ‘Regel’ in the Tractatus fall roughly into five groups. Wittgenstein speaks of Zeichenregeln (sign-rules) at 3.31, 4.241, 6.02, and 6.126, Regeln der logischen Syntax at 3.334 and 3.344, Regeln der Übersetzung (rules of translation) at 3.343 and 4.0141, a Kombinationsregel at 4.442, and in four remarks Wittgenstein mentions rules without obvious classification: 5.47321, 5.476, 5.512, and 5.514.

I will not get to a discussion of rules in the Tractatus until section V. There I will set aside:

  • • Rule of combination, which fixes the sequence of truth-possibilities in a truth table,

  • • Rules of translation from one language into another, which are laws of projection from one language to another,

  • • Remark 5.47321, characterizing Occam’s Razor as not an arbitrary rule, nor a rule justified by practical success.

My focus will be on sign-rules. Even here it is not altogether clear that there is a single notion of sign-rules. In particular, while it’s perhaps relatively clear what are Russell’s sign-rules mentioned in 3.331, it’s not obvious how they are related to the sign-rules said to be definitions in 4.241, of which 6.02 might be an example, or the sign-rules of 6.126. I will suggest, however, that the notion of sign-rule in 6.126 is continuous with the discussion of rules in 5.476, 5.512, and 5.514, and also with rules of logical syntax.

23. A case might be made that in 3.325 Wittgenstein is thinking of rules of logical syntax, despite that fact that the Ramsey-Ogden translation has “A symbolism, that is to say, which obey the rules of logical grammar—of logical syntax” where the published German text has “Eine Zeichensprache also, die der logischen Grammatik—der logischen Syntax—gehorcht.” For, in answer to a query from Ogden about 3.326 Wittgenstein writes of “laws of logical syntax” (1973, 59).

24. This conception is consistent with, if distinct from, Hacker’s view. Hacker holds that the logical syntax of ‘object’ requires it to be used as a variable and rules out its use as a concept word. One might claim that the reason why this is so is that the meaning of ‘object’ is a variable, and variables have the wrong kind of logical valency to combine with the meanings of proper names, which explains why a sentence like ‘the Earth is an object’ is nonsensical.

26. This is just another version of the earlier point that Hacker must think of a rule of logical syntax as specifying a type of use.

27. In this sense the modalities of logic inescapably show forth in our uses and attempts to understand the uses of the signs, irrespective of how we might wish to use them. For more on this idea of our passivity with respect to what shows forth, see Narboux (unpublished).

28. As Proops points out, this is part of the “theory of symbolism” with which Wittgenstein and Russell were preoccupied when Wittgenstein was Russell’s student in Cambridge.

29. As Proops (2000, 10–11) points out, one should distinguish the fact that ‘is green’ occurs to the right of a token of a name in ‘The Sheep Meadow is green in the summer’ from the fact that ‘is green’ occurs to the right of a different token of the same name in ‘After it was watered last week, the Sheep Meadow is green’. Proops proposes using the term ‘token’ to mark this distinction, so that these two sentences both token the fact that ‘is green’ occurs to the right of a name. Thus the sentence in the text should be more carefully formulated as: tokens of facts about occurrences of sign types in the target sentence have the same significance as tokens of the same facts about occurrences of the same sign types in sentences whose meanings we already understand. [End Page 334]

30. “Der wagerechte Strich, aus dem das Zeichen ⊦ gebildet ist, verbindet die darauf folgenden Zeichen zu einem Ganzen, und auf dies Ganze bezieht sich die Bejahung, welche durch den, senkrechten Strich am linken Ende des wagerechten ausgedrückt wird” (Frege 1879, §2, 2).

31. This does not imply that truth is not a property of thought or an object to which thoughts are in some way related. It just means that the acknowledgment of the truth of a thought that is judgment is not analyzable in terms of recognizing that the thought has the property of being true or stands in a relation to truth, because recognizing that something is the case is a (further) judgment. Truth is not fundamentally a property of judgments or thoughts, although it is a property which all correctly judged thoughts have in common. Now, Frege writes, “Jeder Behauptungssatz . . . ist . . . als Eigenname aufzufassen, und zwar ist seine Bedeutung, falls sie vorhanden ist, entweder das Wahre oder das Falsche. Diese beiden Gegenstände werden von jedem, wenn auch nur stillschweigend, anerkannt, der überhaupt urteilt, der etwas für wahr hält, also auch vom Skeptiker” (1967b [1892], 149, op. 34). But there is no conception of what these objects are more fundamental than: the True is the object to which all correctly judged thoughts refer, or to which one intends to refer when, in judging, one takes the step from a thought to a truth-value.

32. There is an interesting partial analogy between this Tractarian view and Kaplan’s theory of directly referential expressions. On Kaplan’s view, what qualifies a term as directly referential has nothing to do with whether it has “descriptive meaning” or not:

Some directly referential terms, like proper names, may have no semantically relevant descriptive meaning, or at least none that is specific: that distinguishes one such term from another. Others, like the indexicals, may have a limited kind of specific descriptive meaning relevant to the features of a context of use. Still others, like ‘dthat’ terms . . . , may be associated with full-blown Fregean senses used to fix the referent

(1989, 497).

What makes these terms directly referential is that their descriptive meaning play no role in determining the truth-value of what we say using them with respect to various possible circumstances. They play a role only in determining the referent which, by itself, is relevant to whether sentences containing them are true or false as descriptions of possible circumstances. In Tractarian terms, the descriptive conditions associated with these terms do not characterize their sense because the correct affirmation and denial of sentences containing them is insensitive to those conditions.

33. Juliet Floyd has argued that one main question that exercises Wittgenstein about Frege’s and Russell’s views of logic is: what are their grounds for their identification of the fundamental truths of logic (2005, 81–84). Floyd mentions the inconsistency of Basic Law V as an urgent reason for Frege to clarify and assess his criteria for being a basic law of logic. I agree, but the problem discussed in the text is a distinct motivation for Wittgenstein’s question.

34. It is thus quite ironic to find a fragment of a letter from Frege to Wittgenstein described as “Reproof, W. lays too great value upon signs” (Floyd 2011, 7).

35. I take this to be at least one way of understanding a number of Juliet Floyd’s remarks about the Tractatus: “There is . . . no such thing as a correct formalism or correct logical notation (richtige Begriffsschrift), either in Frege’s or in Russell’s sense” (1998, 86); “[Wittgenstein’s] aim is to unmask metaphysical idolatry of notation” (2001, 150); “Frege and Russell write as if . . . there is a single context of expression within which we may discern the structure of thought, a systematically presented Begriffsschrift within which we can use logical notation to make perspicuous the logical order. In contrast, I have emphasized Wittgenstein’s insistence in the Tractatus that no single imposition of a logico-syntactic order on what we say is or can be the final word, the final way of expressing or depicting a thought” (2001, 179); “Wittgenstein . . . resisted, the idea that thoughts must be imagined to be expressible, in principle, in a single universally applicable, logically fully perspicuous ‘ideal’ language” (2007, 190–200). Such claims have been taken up as the basis of a so-called “Jacobin” wing or “strong” version of resolution according to which the Tractatus is a wholesale undermining of the idea of a “completely adequate” analysis of the proposition (see Conant and Diamond 2004, 97 n. 82). Needless to say, I don’t think Jacobinism is supported by my account of Tractarian logical necessity. I also don’t think it’s mandatory or fruitful to take it to be expressed in the texts of Floyd I have cited.

36. The term is due to Ricketts (1986).

37. This is not a claim that we find the laws of logic are indubitable, or that we are infallible in accepting the logical laws we accept. Frege is characterizing the commitments we incur if we acknowledge a [End Page 335] thought as a logical law. This characterization is consistent with entertaining doubts, e.g., whether Basic Law V is a law of logic, as Frege apparently did when he wrote volume 1 of Grundgesetze. So Frege was not certain whether to acknowledge V as a logical law, and Russell showed him that he was wrong to do so. But still, in taking the step of acknowledging V, Frege thereby accepts that it makes no sense to doubt whether it is right to use it in any piece of reasoning whatsoever.

REFERENCES

Almog, Joseph. 1989. “Logic and the World.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 18: 197–220.
Aristotle. 1989. Prior Analytics. Translated by Robin Smith. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co.
Baker, Gordon P. 1988. Wittgenstein, Frege, and the Vienna Circle. Oxford: Blackwell.
Conant, James. 2002. “The Method of the Tractatus.” In From Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives on Early Analytic Philosophy. Edited by Erich H. Reck. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 227–51.
Conant, James, and Cora Diamond. 2004. “On Reading the Tractatus Resolutely: Reply to Meredith Williams and Peter Sullivan.” In Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance. Edited by M. Kölbel and B. Weiss. New York: Routledge. 46–99.
Diamond, Cora. 1981. “What Nonsense Might Be.” In The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 95–114.
———. 1984. “What Does a Concept-Script Do?” In The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 115–44.
———. 1988. “Throwing Away the Ladder.” In The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 179–204.
———. 1997. “Realism and Resolution.” Journal of Philosophical Research 22: 75–86.
———. 2002. “Truth before Tarski.” In From Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives on Early Analytic Philosophy. Edited by Erich H. Reck. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 227–51.
———. 2005. “Logical Syntax in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus.” Philosophical Quarterly 55: 78–89.
Dummett, Michael A. E. 1981. Frege: Philosophy of Language. Second Edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Floyd, Juliet. 1998. “The Uncaptive Eye.” In Loneliness. Edited by Leroy S. Rouner. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. 79–108.
———. 2001. “Number and Ascription of Number.” In Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Edited by Juliet Floyd and Sanford Shieh. New York: Oxford University Press. 145–92.
———. 2005. “Wittgenstein on Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics.” In The Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics. Edited by Stewart Shapiro. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 227–87.
———. 2007. “Wittgenstein and the Inexpressible.” In Wittgenstein and the Moral Life: Essays in Honor of Cora Diamond. Edited by Alice Crary. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 177–234.
———. 2011. “Prefatory Note to the Frege-Wittgenstein Correspondence.” In Interactive Wittgenstein. Edited by Enzo de Pellegrin. New York: Springer. 1–14.
Frege, Gottlob. 1879. Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle: L Nebert.
———. 1893. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik: Begriffsschriftlich abgeleitet. vol. 1. Jena: H. Pohle.
———. 1967a. “Begriff und Gegenstand.” In Frege, Kleine Schriften. Edited by I. Angelelli. Hamburg: Felix Meiner. 167–78. Original publication Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie 16 (1892): 192–205.
———. 1967b. “Über Sinn und Bedeutung.” In Frege, Kleine Schriften. Edited by I. Angelelli. Hamburg: Felix Meiner. 143–62. Original publication Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100 (1892): 25–50.
Geach, P. T. 1982. “Truth and God, Part II.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume: 99–115.
Goldfarb, Warren. 1997. “Metaphysics and Nonsense: On Cora Diamond’s The Realistic Spirit.” Journal of Philosophical Research 22: 57–73.
———. 2001. “Frege’s Conception of Logic.” In Future Pasts: The Analytic Tradition in Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Edited by Juliet Floyd and Sanford Shieh. New York: Oxford University Press. 25–41. [End Page 336]
Hacker, P. M. S. 1986. Insight and Illusion: Themes in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein. Second Revised Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 2000. “Was He Trying to Whistle It?” In The New Wittgenstein. Edited by A. Crary and R. Read. London: Routledge. 353–88.
———. 2003. “Wittgenstein, Carnap and the New American Wittgensteinians.” The Philosophical Quarterly 53: 1–23.
Hale, Bob. 1987. Abstract Objects. Oxford: Blackwell.
Kant, Immanuel. 1787. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Second Edition. Riga: Johann Friedrich Hartknoch.
Kaplan, David. 1987. “Demonstratives.” In Themes from Kaplan. Edited by J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 481–564.
Narboux, Jean-Philippe. Unpublished. “Showing Forth.”
Proops, Ian. 2000. Logic and Language in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. New York: Garland.
———. 2001a. “Logical Syntax in the Tractatus.” In Grammar in Early Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Edited by Richard Gaskin. London: Routledge. 161–81.
———. 2001b. “The New Wittgenstein: A Critique.” European Journal of Philosophy 9: 375–404.
Ricketts, Thomas. 1986. “Objectivity and Objecthood: Frege’s Metaphysics of Judgement.” In Frege Synthesized. Edited by Leila Haaparanta and Jaakko Hintikka. Dordrecht: Reidel. 65–95.
———. 1996. “Pictures, Logic, and the Limits of Sense in Wittgenstein’s Tractatus.” In The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein. Edited by Hans Sluga. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 59–99.
———. 2010. “Concepts, Objects and the Context Principle.” In The Cambridge Companion to Frege. Edited by T. Ricketts and M. Potter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 149–219.
Russell, Bertrand. 1903. The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1919. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: G. Allen & Unwin.
———. 1984. Theory of Knowledge: The 1913 Manuscript. London: Routledge.
———. 1994. “Necessity and Possibility.” In The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, volume 4: Logical and Philosophical Papers, 1903–05. Edited by Alasdair Urqhuart and Albert Lewis. London: Routledge. 507–20.
Sullivan, Peter M. 2000. “The Totality of Facts.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100(1): 175–92.
———. 2002. “On Trying to Be Resolute: A Response to Kremer on the Tractatus.” European Journal of Philosophy 10: 43–78.
Whitehead, Alfred North, and Bertrand Russell. 1910. Principia Mathematica. First Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1921. “Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung.” Annalen der Naturphilosophie 14: 185–262.
———. 1973. Letters to C. K. Ogden with comments on the English Translation of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Edited by G. H. von Wright. Oxford: Blackwell.
———. 1979. Notebooks, 1914–1916. Second Edition. Edited by G. H. von Wright and G. E. M. Anscombe. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.
———. 1989. Logische-Philosophische Abhandlung-Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Kritische Edition. Edited by B. F. McGuinness and J. Schulte. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp Verlag. [End Page 337]

Share